Brain and soul pdf. Comments on Chris Frith: Brain and Soul. Exact sciences are objective, inexact sciences are subjective

This book was chosen among other similar ones in order to look at the state of mind of a modern neurophysiologist, recognized as an outstanding one, who, of course, traces all the works on the description of mental phenomena that are sufficiently known today and made an attempt to generalize them, albeit in a popular form, but this after all means - in the most confident form for him.

Fragments of the book where the quotes are taken from are available in the scan archive (1.5 mb). The quotes correctly convey the context that defines the meaning of the book's statements, but if there are inaccuracies, signs of my misunderstanding or unsubstantiated comments, then please leave a message (specifically about this, and not in general) in the discussion below.

It may give the impression of my excessive pickiness. However, on the contrary, he omitted a lot just so as not to get bogged down in trifles.

Quotes from the book highlighted in brown.

So the comments.

I promise that everything I talk about in this book will be convincingly proven by rigorous experimental data. nym. If you would like to see this information for yourself,you will find at the end of the book a detailed list of references to all primary sources.

Unfortunately, a lot of the book is given declaratively, like in a textbook, without directly referring to the actual data, so that it can be impossible to understand where this or that statement comes from. Despite the fact that the book is popular, it clearly claims to be of interdisciplinary value, so it should be possible to see the validity of the assertion.

Our eyes and ears like a video camera, collect information about the material world and convey it to consciousness .

those. camcorder collects information? It is a pity that the word "information" is so carelessly used, and even - as an essence that is transmitted to "consciousness". In the book, signals carrying some kind of information are constantly called information, i.e. information of some significance. In a book that should follow the sequence: signals -> recognition of their significance -> information for response, the most important thing is neglected ... In the fifth chapter there will be an attempt to apply to mental phenomena the "information theory" with which problems with information theory". For example: Theorem Bayes gives us a criterion for judging whether we are adequately using new knowledge- even the concept of "Bayesian brain" is used, which implies the use of this mechanism, and not at all the fundamental criterion of truth - the correspondence of the alleged to the real (it is worth looking at the link what is meant).

It is clear that the book is popular, as it does not require the rigor and correctness of the scientific message, but ... it would be nice if such things (the concepts of information, truth, etc.) were nevertheless taken into account, at least hinted on a correct understanding ... I will try not to pay attention to this in such cases. But here it is, in the same vein:

We need to take a closer look at the relationship between neck psyche and brain. This connection must be close. .... this connection between the brain and the psyche is imperfect.

those. Is there such an entity as the psyche that is connected with the brain? Even in a popular article, such ideas should not be given. Psyche - intangible form processes of the brain (i.e. - what we single out purely subjectively and there is no other such thing in nature - as a kind of essence) and to raise the question of some kind of close connection is absurd. Such liberty is somewhat justified by the phrase: "I am deeply convinced that any changes in the psyche are associated with changes in the activity of the brain.".

Light falls onlight-sensitive cells (photoreceptors) in our eyes, andthey send signals to the brain. The mechanism of this phenomenon is already well known. Then, the activity that occurs in the brain somehow creates a sense of color and shape in our mind. The mechanism of this phenomenon so far completely unknown .

however, in spite of completely unknown "There will be specific statements on this score. In addition, today there are already models of ideas about this mechanism. Although, in fact, they are still far from axiomatic conviction.

Wondering in asking about the brain, and not about consciousness, we can put aside for a whileresolving the issue of how knowledge about the world by fall into our minds . Unfortunately this trick doesn't work. To find out what is known your brain about the environmentre, I would first of all ask to you question: "What do you see?"I appeal to your mind to find out what is displayedis in your brain.

So, having proclaimed a complete misunderstanding of how it happens, let's move on to statements about it.

The person with whom Iworked, the experience gained earlier clearly had a long-terma different effect on the brain, because he was able to do it day by daymore and more successfully complete the task. But these are longthe urgent changes taking place in the brain had no effect on his consciousness. He couldn't remember anything that happened.dealt with him yesterday. The existence of such people testifiesabout what our brains can know about the environmentworld something unknown to our consciousness.

This is a very valuable factual material showing the different mechanism of "motor" learning (formation and correction of unconscious automatisms) and traces of memory left by consciousness.

Expé the immentator asked her to reach out and take hold of this wand.coy. It worked out fine for her. At the same time, she in advanceturned the hand so that it was more convenient to take the wand.At whatever angle the wand is located, it is without problemscould take her hand.This observation shows that the brain D. F . "knows" at what angle the stick is, and cancan use this information to control the movements her hands. In the example, the use of unconscious automatism is observed, i.e. well-adjusted program of action, while:

The experimenter held a stick in his hand and D asked. F ., how this wand is located. She couldn't saydecide whether the stick is horizontal or vertical,or some angle....D. F . cannot use this information to recognize where the wand is located. Her brain knows something about the world around her that her mind does not know..

Unfortunately, before talking about consciousness, nothing is done to at least conditionally define what "consciousness" is.and what is "knowledge" for the brain (cf.about it). It's just that for the time being, everyday representation is used and without hints of something more correctly understood ... And both of these concepts in the context of the book are very important. Accordingly, when trying to compare, there are poor-quality assumptions that "consciousness" may or may not have "knowledge". Only by defining the mechanisms and functions of what outwardly manifests itself as consciousness, one can assert about its properties and abilities. The effect can be generated by completely different reasons that interfere with recognizing the position of the object during awareness (which, apparently, happened once the patient was conscious and did what she was asked to do).

Sometimes a person can be absolutely sure of realitytheir feelings, which are actually false.

...hallucinations associated with schizophrenia have onevery interesting feature. It's not just a false feelingconcerning the material world. Schizophrenics don't just seesome colors and hear some sounds. Their hallucinations themselvesrelate to the phenomena of the psyche ki. They hear voices that aremonitor their actions, give advice and give orders. Our brains are capable of forming false inner worlds of other people.

.... So, if something happens to my brain, my perception of the worldcan no longer be taken at face value.

A rather lengthy text concerning illusions of perception and false belief in reality, both in case of brain damage and illusions of a cognitive nature, is given only as a statement: there are such glitches in the brain. There are no ideas about the mechanisms for correcting recognizers in the brain during adaptive efforts, nor the corresponding loss of elements of such recognition, nor the difference in the unconscious formation of the hierarchy of recognizers and conscious correction (“learning with a teacher” - that is, using consciousness).

But it cannot be said that this question has not been studied at all and remains virginally open. Theoretically, and very close to the realities of the neural network, it is well developed in perceptron models, and there are many works on operating artificial neural networks. Of course, they do not address the very important functionality of consciousness. But consideration of the hierarchy of recognizers in the brain is a very studied area, and it has long been known that the specialization of such recognizers goes far beyond the specifics of sensory areas, but includes such functionality as error, confidence, novelty detectors, i.e. in the form of specific recognizers, everything that we "realize" subjectively is represented, including the feeling "this is invented by me" and "this was perceived in reality". It is quite possible to imagine what will happen if the association of such marks with the image of perception is lost.

At the same time, Chris Frith himself gives examples of the existence of recognizers of such specialized types:

In the parietal lobes of the cortex of somemonkeys (presumably humans too) have neurons thatwhich are activated when the monkey sees something near its hand. It doesn't matter where her brush is at the same time.Neurons are activated when something is from her inclose proximity. Apparently, these neurons indicate the presence of objects that the monkey can reach with his hand.

Of course, everything is complicated by a lack of understanding of how conscious memory is generally represented, among all that is not conscious, although there are many works in this area that allow one to make well-understood holistic assumptions that most likely correspond to the realities of the brain.

For me, the most amazing in these illusions - this is whatthat my brain continues to give me false information even when I know that this information is false, and even when II know what these objects actually look like. I can't stoptwist yourself to see the lines in Hering's illusion as straight.

Chris Frith should remember that the "straight line" recognizers are located in the primary brain region of the visual cortex, and they formed without conscious correction during a critical period of development that preceded the emergence of consciousness. These illusions are the result of misperceptions at a pre-conscious level. However, with the help of consciousness-corrected recognizers, we are able to make sure that the lines are parallel and take this into account in practical activities so that the automatisms that have arisen (no longer conscious skills) will use precisely higher-level recognizers and there will no longer be any illusions that attract attention. But consideration of the features of recognition of different areas of the brain should just touch on the specifics of the book.

But more than that, it turns out: our brainthis opportunity is twofoldth interpretation hides from us and gives us only one of thepossible interpretations. Moreover, sometimes our brain does not take into account at allmania available information about the world.That's what it is - the enemy of our brain :)

Most of us different feelings are completely separated from each other friend. But some people who are called bluesteths, not only hear sounds when sound enters their earswaves, but also feel colors.

Again, for the sake of presentation, reality is neglected? .. There are secondary and tertiary areas of the brain where recognizers use different types receptions transmitted from primary zone recognizers. Complex images are formed there, consisting of different types of receptors. Another thing is that with some pathologies (not necessarily organic), inadequate combinations are possible.

Thus, brain activity indicated that the subject was about to raise his finger in 300 milliseconds before that, as a testMy said that he was going to raise his finger.

From this discovery follows the conclusion that by measuring the activityof your brain, I can find out that you will have a desire underlift your finger before you yourself know about it. This result has sparked so much interest outside of the psychology community.because he seemed to show that even ourthe simplest conscious actions are in fact predetermined. We think we are making a choice, when in fact our brain has already made that choice.. Therefore, the feeling thatthis moment we make a choice, nothing more than an illusion. And ifthe feeling that we are able to make a choice is an illusion, then thatwhat an illusion is our feeling that we have freedom will.

This is an example of the bewilderment that occurs due to the lack of definitions, in this case, the concepts of "we", "consciousness", "choice". The brain is unjustifiably separated from the mechanisms that make it up. The conscious and the unconscious are contrasted, while these are completely inextricably linked phenomena of the organization of memory. The concept of a homunculus clearly dominates, which, unlike the brain, decides something on its own, and it is surprising that it turns out that it is not he who decides, but the brain - this is such an absurdity :) Although further a phrase will flash, as if correcting such an understanding:. .. when we separated brain and consciousness and consideredthem separately, I'll try to put them together again...

Automatisms of perception-action, including automatisms that determine consciousness itself, are inextricably and causally interconnected in the general system of adaptability to new conditions. But, unfortunately, the functions of consciousness are not even close to being presented - as a combination of just such mechanisms, which manifest themselves evolutionarily from the "orienting reflex" and lead to the effect of motivation and "will". Yes, these ideas are far from shared and generally little known. But this is not a reason to believe that they do not exist at all.

In that mo moment when we think we are making a choice in favor of committingactions, our brain has already made this choice .

Actually, you should say: While we are aware of the moment of choice, it has already been largely prepared by the active phases of current automatisms, which does not negate the opportunity, if necessary, to comprehend the problem more deeply, creatively find options for new possible actions and take the risk of implementing them., which is the most important adaptive function of consciousness, and not its simplest mode of tracking the most relevant in perception-action, which is described in this fragment of the book.

The fact that unconscious automatisms continue to monitor what is happening and correct actions is well shown below:

Reach out and graba person can easily and very quickly. But focus here in that in some cases, as soon as the subject begins to extend his hand, the wand moves to a new position.location. The subject can easily correct movementmovement of your hand and accurately grasp the wand in its new positionresearch institutes. In many of these cases, he does not even notice that the stickka has moved. But his brain notices this shift. Handstarts to move in the direction of the original positionwand, and then, about 150 milliseconds afterhow her position changes, the movement of the hand changes,allowing you to grab the wand where it is now. TaHow does our brain notice that the target has moved, andadjusts the movement of the hand to reach the target in its newposition. And all this can happen without us even noticing it. We will not notice any change in the position of the wand,nor change in the movements of one's own hand.

... our brain can make adequateactions, even though We do not see the need for these actions.

Again, the wrong opposition between the brain and us. Skills fixed in automatisms are fundamentally the most adequate, unless new conditions have arisen for which options have not yet been worked out, which is the main function of consciousness.

In other cases, our brain can make adekwadded actions, despite the fact that these actions are differentfrom those that we consider necessary to commit.

Again, this is a question of how applicable skills are to the current situation and if we paid attention to this moment so much so that we doubted, it may turn out that our previous skills will do us a disservice. This is clearly illustrated in the article About dangers.

These observations demonstrate that our body canto interact with the outside world even thenyes, when we ourselves do not know what it does, and even whenour perceptions of the world around us do not correspondreality.

Well, yes, a person in severe alcohol intoxication, "on the machine" can " interact with the environment", get to the house, etc. due to their unconscious automatisms, without the work of consciousness. But it is worth understanding why consciousness is needed at all and, accordingly, not to miss its adaptive functionality, and even in the book, (in fact, and not declaratively) devoted to these issues.

The subject, like his partner, puts the index finger of his right hand on a special mouse. By moving this mouse, you can move move the cursor on the computer screen 1 . This screen has many the gesture of various objects. Through the headphones, the subject heard shit, as someone calls one of these objects. The subject thinks about moving the cursor towards this object. If at this moment his partner (who also receives no instructions via headphones) moves the cursor to the side well, this object, the test subject with a high probabilitymelts that he himself made this movement. Of course, for this experience of fundamental importance is the coincidence in time.

What should prove that... Everything that we we know- that we have an intention to perform some other action, and then, after a while, this action aboutcomes out. Based on this, we we assume that our intention was the cause of the action.

The mechanism for correcting inadequacies (inconsistency between what is supposed and what is received) is not considered at all, and it is precisely this mechanism that is able to correct any of our illusions that lead to a noticeable inadequacy to the level of unconscious automatic execution of actions already without inadequacies, .

Do you know aboutbe anything? What remains of "you" if you do not feel your own body and are not aware of your own actions? ... how are things going with actions that require thought, then mu that you find yourself in a new situation and cannot resortgo to completed operations ?

Here! this is already an approach to the functionality of consciousness. The following describes the basic criteria for fixing positive and negative experiences that correct our behavior, adapting it to reality:

Pavlov showed that any stimulus can become a signal for the appearance of food and cause animals to strive for this stimulus .... In addition, Pavlov showed that exactly the same learning occurs if punishment is used instead of a reward. If you put something unpleasant in your dog's mouth, he will try to get rid of it by shaking his head, opening his mouth and working his tongue (as well as salivating) .... Pavlov found an experimental method that allows him to explore the most basic forms of learning ... This mechanism allows us to learn what things are pleasant to us and what are unpleasant .... We also need to learn what to do to get pleasant things, and what to do to avoid unpleasant things.

The main sign of the need to correct the experience is correctly noted:

If a... the signal tells us nothing new, so we do not pay attention to it attention .

But ... a decisive generalization, a complete picture does not occur ....

Instead, wandering in dead-end directions begins:

Wolfram Schultz tracked the activity of these cells in an experiment to form conditioned reflex and discovered that they were not actually reward cells. In this experiment, one second after an extraneous, as in Pavlov's experiments, signal (light flash), a portion of fruit juice was injected into the monkey's mouth. Initially, dopamine nerve cells played the role of reward cells, reacting to the intake of juice, but after the training was over, they ceased to be activated at the time of the injection of juice. Instead, they now fired immediately after the monkey saw the flash, a second before the juice arrived. Apparently, the excitation of dopamine cells served as a signal that the juice should be received soon. They did not respond to the award, but predicted to receive .

It was not taken into account in any way that Pavlov considered "anticipatory excitation" as predictive mechanisms in the same place. And the ability to foresee depends on the richness of life skills in different situations, which, during the awareness of the situation, occurs in the form of predictive preexcitations.

The quotation refers to the separation by means of neurotransmitters of different response styles for different conditions, i.e. refers to the emotional context of a behavior. Of course, the emotional context highlights those parts of the neural network that were formed with the participation of a given neurotransmitter, and it is they that come to the fore among all prognostic subexcitations in a given emotional state(It should also be taken into account that, in addition to the neurotransmitter separation of emotional contexts, more particular contexts are being developed based on the separation of attention).

And, of course, it is not neurotransmitters that serve as a reward or punishment. For this, special recognizers of the significance system , . It is their irritation that causes the appearance of one or another state of significance, positive or negative, and not very important cells that secrete the neurotransmitter dopamine. These cells are often referred to as reward cells. when the rat will willingly press the lever.So here Chris Frith is a big mess, and hoping for a good, holistic generalization in this case there is no chance. Yes, he directly contradicts himself, confirming:The activity of these cells does not serve as a reward signal.

Phrase-apotheosis: dopamine activitynerve cells serve as a signal of error in our prediction niyakh - a far departure from the actual mechanisms, and there is not even an attempt to bring everything into a single non-contradictory system ...

Thus our brain studiesassign a certain value all events, objectthere and places in the world around us. Many of them at this remain indifferent to us, but many acquired value high or low.

In fact, only a part of the brain is engaged in this, representing the mechanisms of consciousness and the development of new (correcting old) reactions in new conditions. And, of course, not everything in perception, but only in its conscious part, at moments of awareness, is involved in the mechanisms of such an assessment.

At the same time, Chris Frith does not deliberately blurt out about emotions right there, and this is already happening with him more reasonably:

We experience sensations that reflect this value card tei, enclosed in our brain when we return from the valleytrip abroad: we feel a rush of emotions, growing as the streets we move throughbecome more and more familiar.

But it turns out that this map of values ​​is presented as something in the form of a separately existing model:

The brain mapsthe surrounding world. Essentially, it is a value map. On the objects of high value are marked on this map tew, promising a reward, and objects of low value, promising punishment. It also highlights high-value actions that promise success, and actions of low value that promise failure.

If we take into account that there are ancient structures in the brain, the activation of which directly shows their purpose as primary recognizers of positive or negative significance, if we take into account that all recognizers of the primary areas of the brain eventually converge into complex recognizers with representation of all primary ones, then it was It would not be difficult to assume that there is no special part of the brain for constructing a certain map of the world in the form of a relationship to it, but simply that all tertiary recognizers have an association with significance recognizers. Of course, all this is not an end in itself, but is used in chains of behavioral automatisms (which include the automatisms of thinking, i.e., those that form the redistribution of attention, and do not have access to effector reactions). The model of the world, consistent with the significance attached to the acts of awareness, is the automatisms of life experience, branching for all the specific conditions for their implementation of any greatest complexity, which do not require awareness in already known situations. Associated with each phase of automatisms of significance and direct their development or inhibit them for a given emotional context and perception-action. That's why As soon as I see that mug over there, my brain alreadystarts to play with muscles and bend my fingers in case euif I want to take it in my hand.

not a picture at all.

“Are you saying,” she replies, “that somewhere in my brain there are maps of all the places I have ever been, and instinstructions how to get my hands on all the objects that I have ever seen?"

I explain to her that this, probably, is the most important thing.a remarkable feature of these learning algorithms.

Patient I. W . as a result of a viral infection completely sweatryal the sensitivity of the limbs ...He knows the position of hislimbs only when he can see them. People from tosuch brain damage usually do not move, not lookto the fact that they can still control their muscles ....After many years of exercisehard work, he learned to walk again, although hedrops immediately when the light is turned off. He learned to takethrows with his hand, if he sees both the object itself and his hand .... These movements are not no automatic corrections are made . From start to finishfor any action, he has to consciously control every movement.

Here is another fragment that requires an understanding of the functionality of consciousness. Movement programs are developed in early age during the corresponding critical period of development and then only corrected, remaining unchanged in the basic elements. Each phase of muscle movement uses the same muscle receptors to be used as a starting stimulus for the transition to the next phase, forming chains of motor automatisms. In order to change them, to correct them for the new conditions, awareness is necessary, those same "mental efforts". But if muscle receptors are damaged, then all programs will not work. It is necessary to relearn at the most basic level of the simplest movements with the participation of consciousness. However, the critical period for the optimal passage of such training has long passed, and it requires constant effort, as if the maguli were trying to teach them to speak. In fact, automatisms, nevertheless, are formed, chains are already formed on the basis of visual signals. But it's very difficult.

Our perceptions depend on a priori beliefs.... Our perception is actually starts from within - from a priori conviction, whichis a model of the world where objects occupy certainlazy position in space. Using this model, our brain can predict what signals should come.into our eyes and ears. These predictions are compared with realsignals, and at the same time, of course,errors. But our brain only welcomes them. These mistakes teachhis perception. The presence of such errors tells him that histhe model of the surrounding world is not good enough. Characterbug tells him how to make a model that will be betterformer. As a result, the cycle repeats again and again, until the errors become negligible. For this, usuallyjust a few such cycles are enough for the brain tomay be required only 100 milliseconds .

And as if they forgot what was said earlier, that much more time is required for awareness:

It was so far It is known that some unconsciously perceived objects can have a small effect on our behavior. Butit is difficult to demonstrate this effect. To make sure that the subject did not realize that he saw some object, heshow very quickly and "mask" it, right after thatshowing another object in the same place.... If the interval betweenfirst person and second person less than approximately 40 milliseconds,the subject does not realize that he saw the first person.

So these cycles of adjustment are out of awareness? But, of course, as was recently stated, with the use of neurotransmitters? ... And if a person woke up and while he perception is not starts from within? Is he doomed not to recognize anything in his surroundings? Again, some kind of absurd dead end ... While the window of a holistic and interconnected understanding is nearby. Understanding is formed by a hierarchy of perceptual contexts (see Understanding Context). Primary recognizers give primitives to secondary ones, significance recognizers recognize important features and prepare the emotional context of perception-action, which begins to determine the style of behavior and how the perceived will be interpreted.

We can't We can perceive nothing without knowledge, but we cannot know anything without perception. Where does our brain get the a priori knowledge it needs tofor perception? Part of this is innate knowledge written downin our brains over millions of years of evolution. Here are some assumptions to be made. And all this knowledge must fit into a very limited space. genetic code. There is a lot to take into account hereinheritance possibilities: trait inheritance.

How do we know what is real and what is not?how does our brain know when we actually see a face and when we just imagine it? In both cases, the brain creates an image of the face. How do we know one hundredIs there a real person behind this model? This issue appliesnot only to persons, but also to anything else.

But this problem is solved very simple. When we are onlyimagine a face in our brain no signals from sense organs with which he could compare hislegends. No errors are tracked either. When we see a real face, a model created by our brain,always turns out to be a little imperfect .

Here is another example of forced simplification, conjectures in the absence of understanding of the mechanisms... However, even from memory, without observing, we perfectly distinguish between those images that we actually saw and what we invented ourselves. So this hypothesis a no longer withstands criticism. And there is no need to continue to deepen the criticism of this absurdity. Again, the simplest thing is forgotten: the fact that literally all subjective sensations are represented by specialized recognizers (associated with the significance of what is perceived in given conditions), the activity of which is associated with the image of perception. What we imagined - with the label "I invented it," and what is perceived by the senses - with the label "I really observed it." And such associations can be lost for one reason or another (the most important of which is the significance associated with them, which can be overestimated), leading to a confusion of reality and reality. All this, upon comprehension, is fixed into the memory chain of the current perception (the mental chain) in the entire set of associated activities of recognizers, allowing subsequently to access such memory (and modifying it with each such access).

It turns out that's why Our imagination is completely uncreative. It doesn'tpredictions and does not correct errors. We do nothing in our head. We create by giving form to our thoughts.throws, strokes and drafts, allowing us to extractbenefit from surprises with which reality is full.Again, far from such an understanding: Basic Mechanisms of Creativity.

Perhaps the attempt to talk about the imagination was the most deplorable. Probably because imagination and imagination skills, more precisely, creativity, are part of the mechanisms for generating new behaviors - the mechanisms of consciousness. And Chris Frith deliberately avoids this topic:

Like from our mother's activitycan subjective experience arise in the brain? It wasMany solutions to this problem have been proposed, but none of them has proven to be entirely satisfactory. I knew that I hadnothing better will come of it. Therefore, this book is not so much aboutknowing how much about the brain. Instead of writing about consciousness, I paid special attention toattention to how much our brain knows without our knowing.

Those. this declared that the book is purely about the already accumulated unconscious automatisms. Which, in general, in fact, according to the text, is far from the case ... All the same, we are not insects and not lobotomized (not automata) and, considering the system of significance, emotions, motivation, "will" that provides trial behavior contrary to previously fixed unconscious assessments, it is impossible to get around why everything was created by evolution and how it is all aimed at the only thing: the development of those automatisms already tested by personal experience for conditions in which previous experience gives the unexpected and not desirable, or experience suggests uncertainty for these conditions.

And wherein:

Seems Xia that there is very little left for consciousness. Vmeone hundred to wonder how subjective experience may arise from the activity of neurons, I want to ask the question: " Why consciousness is needed?"

So, why do we need something for which there are “so few things to do”, but for some reason it has evolved long ago not only in humans? Here, it turns out why (of all the following text, the most claiming to be the answer was chosen):

This last illusion created by our brain is that we exist separately from the social environment.we are free agents, allows us to create together societies and cultures that are so much morethan each of us individually .... If our predictions about other people are correct, so we succeededread their minds. But all this complex activity is hiddenfrom U.S. This shouldn't bother us. Let's get back on ve blueberry and we'll have fun.

Summary.

On the example of Chris Frith's book, we have to admit that modern researchers of mental phenomena are still far from a holistic view of the mechanisms of the psyche, they do not have a plausible picture of the interconnections of these mechanisms based on a huge number of facts obtained, which makes it possible to connect everything not in an isolated fragmentary way, but consistently throughout collections of data.

In the 50s or so, many neuroscientists begin to feel that they have accumulated enough wisdom and experience to tackle the problem of consciousness. As neuroscientists, they seek to identify processes in the nervous system associated with consciousness, and show how subjective experience can arise from the activity of our material brain. Many solutions to this problem have been proposed, but none of them has proven to be entirely satisfactory. I knew I couldn't do better. So this book is not so much about consciousness as it is about the brain.

On the whole, the book is reminiscent of pop works such as Amazing Chemistry Experiments: a description of the bizarre effects of the psyche without the slightest attempt to show their interrelationships and integral mechanisms. Most of the attention is paid to this, minor details are savored and ... that's it.

There is not only no chance to create a complete picture, but even to understand how consistent and plausible other people's generalizations are. The fact is that to capture the essence of the organization of a neural network, which represents the most complex physical and chemical formation, to single out adaptive functionality from the auxiliary at the level of interconnected local algorithms, to assess the plausibility of generalizing assumptions, sifting out what is not sufficiently interconnected and secondary, requires just such worldview base.

When I was in school, chemistry was the worst for me. met.....

Knowledge of only physiology extremely narrows the possibilities of generalization to ideas that do not go far beyond the framework of physiology, which is clearly observed in many generations of physiologists who are trying to holistically describe the mechanisms of mental phenomena.

© Chris D. Frith, 2007

All Rights Reserved. Authorized translation from the English language edition published by Blackwell Publishing Limited. Responsibility for the accuracy of the translation rests solely with The Dynasty Foundation and is not the responsibility of John Blackwell Publishing Limited. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form without the written permission of the original copyright holder, Blackwell Publishing Limited.

© Dmitry Zimin Dynasty Foundation, Russian edition, 2010

© P. Petrov, translation into Russian, 2010

© Astrel Publishing LLC, 2010

CORPUS® Publishing


All rights reserved. No part of the electronic version of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any means, including posting on the Internet and corporate networks, for private and public use, without the written permission of the copyright owner.


© Electronic version of the book prepared by Litres (www.litres.ru)

* * *

Dedicated to Uta

List of abbreviations

ACT - axial computed tomography

MRI - magnetic resonance imaging

PET - positron emission tomography

fMRI - functional magnetic resonance imaging

EEG - electroencephalogram

BOLD (blood oxygenation level dependent)

Foreword

I have an amazing labor-saving device in my head. My brain - better than a dishwasher or a calculator - frees me from the boring, repetitive work of recognizing things around me and even saves me from having to think about how to control the movements of my body. This gives me the opportunity to focus on what is really important to me: friendship and the exchange of ideas. But, of course, my brain not only saves me from a tedious daily work. It is he who forms me who lives in the company of other people. In addition, it is my brain that allows me to share with my friends the fruits of my inner world. So the brain makes us capable of something more than what each of us is capable of individually. This book is about how the brain performs these miracles.

Thanks

My work on the mind and brain was made possible by funding from the Medical Research Council and the Wellcome Trust. The Medical Research Council enabled me to work in the neurophysiology of schizophrenia through financial support from the Tim Crow Psychiatric Unit at the Northwick Park Hospital Clinical Research Center in London, Harrow, Middlesex. At that time, we could judge the relationship between the psyche and the brain only on the basis of indirect data, but everything changed in the eighties, when tomographs were invented to scan the working brain.

The Wellcome Trust enabled Richard Frackowiak to set up the Functional Imaging Laboratory and financially supported my work in this laboratory on the neurophysiological basis of consciousness and social interactions. The study of mind and brain is at the intersection of many traditional disciplines, from anatomy and computational neuroscience to philosophy and anthropology. I have been very fortunate to have always worked in interdisciplinary – and multinational – research groups.

I have benefited a lot from my colleagues and friends at University College London, especially Ray Dolan, Dick Passingham, Daniel Wolpert, Tim Shallis, John Driver, Paul Burgess and Patrick Haggard. In the early stages of writing this book, I was aided by many fruitful discussions about the brain and psyche with my friends in Aarhus, Jakob Howu and Andreas Röpstorff, and in Salzburg with Josef Perner and Heinz Wimmer. Martin Frith and John Law have, for as long as I can remember, argued with me about everything in question in this book. Eva Johnstone and Sean Spence generously shared with me their professional knowledge about psychiatric phenomena and their implications for brain science.

Perhaps the most important impetus for writing this book came from my weekly conversations with past and present breakfast parties. Sarah-Jane Blakemore, Davina Bristow Thierry Chaminade, Jenny Kull, Andrew Duggins, Chloe Farrer, Helen Gallagher, Tony Jack, James Kilner, Haguan Lau, Emiliano Macaluso, Eleanor Maguire, Pierre Macke, Jen Marchant, Dean Mobbs, Matthias Pessilone, Chiara Portas, Geraint Rees, Johannes Schultz, Suchy Shergill, and Tanya Singer helped shape this book. I am deeply grateful to all of them.

To Karl Friston and Richard Gregory, who have read portions of this book, I am grateful for their invaluable help and valuable advice. I am also grateful to Paul Fletcher for supporting the idea of ​​introducing an English professor and other characters who argue with the narrator early on in the book.

Philip Carpenter selflessly contributed to the improvement of this book with his critical remarks.

I am especially grateful to those who read all the chapters and commented in detail on my manuscript. Sean Gallagher and two anonymous readers have made many valuable suggestions for improving the text of this book. Rosalind Ridley made me think carefully about my statements and be careful with terminology. Alex Frith helped me get rid of professional jargon and lack of coherence.

Uta Frith actively participated in this project at all its stages. If she had not set an example and guided me, this book would never have seen the light of day.

Prologue: Real Scientists Don't Study Consciousness

Why psychologists are afraid of parties

Like any other tribe, scientists have their own hierarchy. The place of psychologists in this hierarchy is at the very bottom. I discovered this in my freshman year at university where I was studying science. We have been told that college students - for the first time - will have the opportunity in the first part of the course natural sciences practice psychology. Encouraged by this news, I went to our group leader to ask him what he knew about this new opportunity. “Yes,” he replied. “But it never crossed my mind that one of my students would be so dumb as to want to study psychology.” He himself was a physicist.

Because, probably, that I was not quite sure what "stupid" meant, this remark did not stop me. I left physics and took up psychology. From then until now, I have continued to study psychology, but I have not forgotten my place in the scientific hierarchy. At parties where scientists gather, from time to time the question inevitably pops up: “What do you do?” - and I tend to think twice before answering, "I'm a psychologist."

Of course, much has changed in psychology in the last 30 years. We borrowed a lot of methods and concepts from other disciplines. We study not only behavior, but also the brain. We use computers to analyze our data and model mental processes. 1
Although I must admit that there are some retrogrades who generally deny that the study of the brain or computers can tell us anything about our psyche. - Note. ed.

My university badge doesn't say "psychologist" but "cognitive neuroscientist."


Rice. item 1.General form and a slice of the human brain

Human brain, side view (top). The arrow marks the place where the cut shown in Fig. bottom photo. The outer layer of the brain (cortex) consists of gray matter and forms many folds that allow you to fit a large surface area in a small volume. The cortex contains about 10 billion nerve cells.


And they ask me: “What do you do?” It seems to be the new head of the physics department. Unfortunately, my response “I am a cognitive neuroscientist” only delays the denouement. After my attempts to explain what, in fact, my work consists, she says: “Ah, so you are a psychologist!” - with that characteristic facial expression in which I read: “If only you could do real science!”.

A professor of English joins the conversation and raises the topic of psychoanalysis. She has a new student who "doesn't agree with Freud in many ways." In order not to spoil my evening, I refrain from suggesting that Freud was an inventor, and that his discussions about the human psyche are of little relevance to the case.

A few years ago, the editor of the British Psychiatric Journal ( British Journal of Psychiatry), apparently by mistake, asked me to write a review of a Freudian article. I was immediately struck by one subtle difference from the articles I usually review. As in any scientific article, there were many references to the literature. Basically, these are links to works on the same topic, published earlier. We refer to them partly in order to pay tribute to the achievements of their predecessors, but mainly in order to support certain statements that are contained in our own work. “You don't have to take my word for it. You can read a detailed rationale for the methods I used in Box and Cox (Box and Cox, 1964).” 2
Believe it or not, this is a reference to a genuine work that substantiates an important statistical method. Bibliographic data of this work can be found in the bibliography at the end of the book. - Note. ed.

But the authors of this Freudian article did not at all try to back up the cited facts with references. References to the literature were not about facts, but about ideas. Using references, it was possible to trace the development of these ideas in the writings of various followers of Freud up to the original words of the teacher himself. At the same time, no facts were cited by which it would be possible to judge whether his ideas were fair.

“Freud may have had a great influence on literary criticism,” I tell the professor of English, “but he was not a real scientist. He was not interested in facts. I study psychology by scientific methods.”

“So,” she replies, “you are using a monster of machine intelligence to kill the human in us.” 3
She is a specialist in the work of Australian writer Elizabeth Costello. - Note. ed.(Australian writer Elizabeth Costello is a fictional character in the book of the same name by South African writer John Maxwell Coetzee. – Note. transl.)

On both sides of the abyss that separates our views, I hear the same thing: "Science cannot investigate consciousness." Why can't?

Exact and inexact sciences

In the system of scientific hierarchy, "exact" sciences occupy a high position, and "inexact" - low. The subjects studied by the exact sciences are like a cut diamond, which has a strictly defined shape, and all parameters can be measured with high accuracy. "Inexact" sciences study objects that look like an ice cream ball, the shape of which is far from being so definite, and the parameters can change from measurement to measurement. The exact sciences, such as physics and chemistry, study tangible objects that can be measured with great precision. For example, the speed of light (in a vacuum) is exactly 299,792,458 meters per second. A phosphorus atom weighs 31 times more than a hydrogen atom. These are very important numbers. Based on the atomic weight of various elements, one can compose periodic table, which once made it possible to draw the first conclusions about the structure of matter at the subatomic level.

Once biology was not such an exact science as physics and chemistry. This state of affairs changed dramatically after scientists discovered that genes consist of strictly defined sequences of nucleotides in DNA molecules. For example, the sheep prion gene 4
sheep prion- a protein, the modified configuration of the molecules of which causes the development of a disease in sheep, similar to the disease of a mad cow. - Note. transl.

It consists of 960 nucleotides and begins like this:

I must admit that in the face of such precision and rigor, psychology looks like a very imprecise science. The most famous number in psychology is 7, the number of things that can be held in working memory at the same time. 5
working memory is a type of active short term memory. This is the memory that we use when we try to remember a phone number without writing it down. Psychologists and neuroscientists are actively researching working memory, but have yet to agree on exactly what they are researching. - Note. ed.

But even this figure needs to be clarified. An article by George Miller about this discovery, published in 1956, was titled “ magic number seven plus or minus two. Therefore, the best measurement result obtained by psychologists can vary in one direction or another by almost 30%. The number of items we can hold in working memory varies from time to time and from person to person. In a state of fatigue or anxiety, I will remember fewer numbers. I speak English and therefore can remember more numbers than those who speak Welsh. 6
This statement is not at all a manifestation of some kind of prejudice against the Welsh. It is about one of important discoveries made by psychologists who have studied working memory. Welsh speakers remember fewer numbers because it takes longer to say the names of a series of numbers in Welsh than it does to say the names of the same numbers in English. - Note. ed.

“What did you expect? says the professor of English. “The human soul cannot be straightened out like a butterfly in a shop window. Each of us is unique.”

This remark is not entirely appropriate. Of course, each of us is unique. But we all have general properties psyche. It is these fundamental properties that psychologists are looking for. Chemists had exactly the same problem with the substances they investigated before the discovery. chemical elements in the 18th century. Each substance is unique. Psychology, compared to the "exact" sciences, had little time to find what to measure and figure out how to measure. Psychology as a scientific discipline has only existed for a little over 100 years. I am sure that in time psychologists will find what to measure and develop devices that will help us make these measurements very accurate.

Exact sciences are objective, inexact sciences are subjective

These optimistic words are based on my belief in the unstoppable progress of science. 7
The professor of English does not share this belief. - Note. auth.

But, unfortunately, in the case of psychology, there are no solid grounds for such optimism. What we are trying to measure is qualitatively different from what is measured in the exact sciences.

In the exact sciences, the results of measurements are objective. They can be checked. “Don't believe that the speed of light is 299,792,458 meters per second? Here's your equipment. Measure yourself!” When we use this measurement equipment, the results will appear on dials, printouts and computer screens where anyone can read them. And psychologists use themselves or their volunteer assistants as measuring instruments. The results of such measurements are subjective. You can't check them.

Here is a simple psychological experiment. I run a program on my computer that shows a field of black dots continuously moving down from the top of the screen to the bottom. I stare at the screen for a minute or two. Then I press "Escape" and the dots stop moving. Objectively, they no longer move. If I put the tip of a pencil on one of them, I can make sure that this point is definitely not moving. But I still have a very strong subjective feeling that the dots are slowly moving up. 8
This phenomenon is known as the waterfall effect or motion aftereffect. If we look at the waterfall for a minute or two and then look at the bushes on the side of it, there is a distinct feeling that the bushes are moving up, despite the fact that we clearly see that they remain in place. - Note. ed.

If at that moment you were to enter my room, you would see fixed points on the screen. I would tell you that it seems to me that the dots are moving up, but how do you check this? After all, their movement occurs only in my head.

A real scientist wants to independently and independently verify the results of measurements reported by others. Nullius in verba 9
Literally: "No one's words" (lat.). – Note. transl.

- this is the motto of the Royal Society of London: "Do not believe what others tell you, no matter how high their authority is." 10
“Nullius addictus jurare in verba magistri” - “Without swearing allegiance to the words of any teacher” (Horace, “Messages”). - Note. ed.

If I followed this principle, I would have to agree that a scientific investigation of your inner world is impossible for me, because for this I have to rely on what you tell me about your inner experience.

For a while, psychologists pretended to be real scientists by only studying behavior—taking objective measurements of things like movements, button presses, reaction times. 11
These were followers of behaviorism, a trend whose most famous representatives were John Watson and Burres Frederick Skinner. The zeal with which they promoted their approach indirectly indicates that all is not well with him. One of the professors I studied with in college was a passionate behaviorist who later became a psychoanalyst. - Note. ed.

But behavioral research is by no means enough. Such studies leave out everything that is most interesting in our personal experience. We all know that our inner world no less real than our life in the material world. Unrequited love brings no less suffering than a burn from touching a hot stove. 12
Moreover, judging by the results of tomographic studies, the same part of the brain is involved in the reactions of physical pain and suffering of a rejected person. - Note. ed.

The work of consciousness can influence the results of physical actions that can be objectively measured. For example, if you imagine that you are playing the piano, the quality of your performance may improve. So why shouldn't I take your word for it that you imagined playing the piano? Now we psychologists have returned to the study of subjective experience: sensations, memories, intentions. But the problem has not gone away: the mental phenomena that we study have a completely different status than the material phenomena that other scientists study. Only from your words can I learn about what is going on in your mind. You press a button to let me know you've seen a red light. Can you tell me what shade that red was. But there is no way I can get into your mind and check for myself how red was the light that you saw.

For my friend Rosalind, each number has a specific position in space, and each day of the week has its own color (see Fig. CV1 in the color inset). But maybe these are just metaphors? I have never experienced anything like it. Why should I believe her when she says that these are her immediate, uncontrollable sensations? Her sensations relate to the phenomena of the inner world, which I can not verify in any way.

Will big science help inexact science?

Exact science becomes “big science” 13
big science” (big science) - expensive scientific research involving large scientific teams (a colloquial term in modern English). - Note. transl.

When it starts to use very expensive measuring instruments. The science of the brain went big when CT scanners were developed to scan the brain in the last quarter of the 20th century. One such scanner usually costs more than a million pounds. Through sheer luck, being in right time in the right place, I got the opportunity to use these devices when they first appeared, in the mid-eighties 14
The decision of the Medical Research Council to close the Clinical Research Center, where I had been working on schizophrenia for many years, prompted me to take a risk and significantly change the direction of my psychological research. Subsequently, both the Medical Research Council and the Wellcome Trust have shown a high degree foresight by providing financial support for new encephalographic research. - Note. ed.

The first such devices were based on the long-established principle of fluoroscopy. An x-ray machine can show bones inside your body because bones are much harder (dense) than skin and soft tissues. Similar density differences are observed in the brain. The skull surrounding the brain has a very high density, while the density of the tissues of the brain itself is much less. In the depths of the brain are cavities (ventricles) filled with fluid, they have the lowest density. A breakthrough in this field came with the development of axial computed tomography (ACT) technology and the construction of an ACT scanner. This apparatus uses X-rays to measure density and then decides huge number equations (which requires a powerful computer) and builds a three-dimensional image of the brain (or any other part of the body), reflecting differences in density. Such a device for the first time made it possible to see the internal structure of the brain of a living person - a voluntary participant in the experiment.

A few years later, another method was developed, even better than the previous one - magnetic resonance imaging (MRI). MRI does not use X-rays, but radio waves and a very strong magnetic field. 15
Don't think I really understand how MRI works, but here's one physicist who does: J.P. Hornak, The Basics of MRI(“Fundamentals of MRI”), http://www.cis.rit.edu/htbooks/mri/index.html. – Note. ed.

Unlike fluoroscopy, this procedure is not at all dangerous to health. An MRI scanner is much more sensitive to density differences than an ACT scanner. On the images of the brain of a living person, obtained with its help, we can distinguish different types fabrics. The quality of such images is not lower than the quality of photographs of the brain, after death, removed from the skull, preserved with chemicals and cut into thin layers.


Rice. item 2. An example of an MRI structural image of the brain and a section of the brain removed from a corpse

Above is a photograph of one of the sections of the brain, removed from the skull after death and cut into thin layers. Below is an image of one of the layers of the brain of a living person, obtained by magnetic resonance imaging (MRI).


Structural tomography of the brain has played a huge role in the development of medicine. Brain injuries from road traffic accidents, strokes, or tumor growth can have a profound effect on behavior. They can lead to severe memory loss or serious personality changes. Before the advent of CT scanners, the only way to find out exactly where an injury occurred was to remove the skull cap and look. Usually this was done after death, but sometimes in a living patient - when a neurosurgical operation was required. Now tomographs allow you to accurately determine the location of the injury. All that is required of the patient is to lie motionless inside the tomograph for 15 minutes.


Rice. item 3. An example of an MRI scan showing brain damage

This patient suffered two strokes in a row, as a result of which the auditory cortex of the right and left hemispheres was destroyed. The injury is clearly visible on the MRI image.


Structural tomography of the brain is both an exact and a big science. Measurements of the structural parameters of the brain, carried out using these methods, can be very accurate and objective. But what do these measurements have to do with the problem of psychology as an "inexact" science?

Chris Frith

The famous British neurophysiologist Chris Frith is well known for his ability to talk simply about very difficult problems psychology such as mental activity, social behavior, autism and schizophrenia. It is in this area, along with the study of how we perceive the world around us, act, make choices, remember and feel, that today there is a scientific revolution associated with the introduction of neuroimaging methods. In Brain and Soul, Chris Frith talks about all this in the most accessible and entertaining way.

Chris Frith

Brain and soul. How neural activity shapes our inner world

© Chris D. Frith, 2007

All Rights Reserved. Authorized translation from the English language edition published by Blackwell Publishing Limited. Responsibility for the accuracy of the translation rests solely with The Dynasty Foundation and is not the responsibility of John Blackwell Publishing Limited. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form without the written permission of the original copyright holder, Blackwell Publishing Limited.

© Dmitry Zimin Dynasty Foundation, Russian edition, 2010

© P. Petrov, translation into Russian, 2010

© Astrel Publishing LLC, 2010

CORPUS® Publishing

All rights reserved. No part of the electronic version of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any means, including posting on the Internet and corporate networks, for private and public use, without the written permission of the copyright owner.

© The electronic version of the book was prepared by Litres (www.litres.ru (http://www.litres.ru/))

Dedicated to Uta

List of abbreviations

ACT - axial computed tomography

MRI - magnetic resonance imaging

PET - positron emission tomography

fMRI - functional magnetic resonance imaging

EEG - electroencephalogram

BOLD (blood oxygenation level dependent)

Foreword

I have an amazing labor-saving device in my head. My brain - better than a dishwasher or a calculator - frees me from the boring, repetitive work of recognizing things around me and even saves me from having to think about how to control the movements of my body. This gives me the opportunity to focus on what is really important to me: friendship and the exchange of ideas. But, of course, my brain doesn't just save me from tedious daily work. It is he who forms the me, whose life takes place in the society of other people. In addition, it is my brain that allows me to share with my friends the fruits of my inner world. So the brain makes us capable of something more than what each of us is capable of individually. This book is about how the brain performs these miracles.

Thanks

My work on the mind and brain was made possible by funding from the Medical Research Council and the Wellcome Trust. The Medical Research Council enabled me to work in the neurophysiology of schizophrenia through financial support from the Tim Crow Psychiatric Unit at the Northwick Park Hospital Clinical Research Center in London, Harrow, Middlesex. At that time, we could judge the relationship between the psyche and the brain only on the basis of indirect data, but everything changed in the eighties, when tomographs were invented to scan the working brain. The Wellcome Trust enabled Richard Frackowiak to set up the Functional Imaging Laboratory and financially supported my work in this laboratory on the neurophysiological basis of consciousness and social interactions. The study of mind and brain is at the intersection of many traditional disciplines, from anatomy and computational neuroscience to philosophy and anthropology. I have been very fortunate to have always worked in interdisciplinary – and multinational – research groups.

I have benefited a lot from my colleagues and friends at University College London, especially Ray Dolan, Dick Passingham, Daniel Wolpert, Tim Shallis, John Driver, Paul Burgess and Patrick Haggard. In the early stages of writing this book, I was aided by many fruitful discussions about the brain and psyche with my friends in Aarhus, Jakob Howu and Andreas Röpstorff, and in Salzburg with Josef Perner and Heinz Wimmer. Martin Frith and John Law have been arguing with me for as long as I can remember about everything in this book. Eva Johnstone and Sean Spence generously shared with me their professional knowledge of psychiatric phenomena and their implications for brain science.

Perhaps the most important impetus for writing this book came from my weekly conversations with past and present breakfast parties. Sarah-Jane Blakemore, Davina Bristow Thierry Chaminade, Jenny Kull, Andrew Duggins, Chloe Farrer, Helen Gallagher, Tony Jack, James Kilner, Haguan Lau, Emiliano Macaluso, Eleanor Maguire, Pierre Macke, Jen Marchant, Dean Mobbs, Matthias Pessilone, Chiara Portas, Geraint Rees, Johannes Schultz, Suchy Shergill, and Tanya Singer helped shape this book. I am deeply grateful to all of them.

To Karl Friston and Richard Gregory, who have read portions of this book, I am grateful for their invaluable help and valuable advice. I am also grateful to Paul Fletcher for supporting the idea of ​​introducing an English professor and other characters who argue with the narrator early on in the book.

Philip Carpenter selflessly contributed to the improvement of this book with his critical remarks.

I am especially grateful to those who read all the chapters and commented in detail on my manuscript. Sean Gallagher and two anonymous readers have made many valuable suggestions for improving the text of this book. Rosalind Ridley made me think carefully about my statements and be careful with terminology. Alex Frith helped me get rid of professional jargon and lack of coherence.

Uta Frith actively participated in this project at all its stages. If she had not set an example and guided me, this book would never have seen the light of day.

Prologue: Real Scientists Don't Study Consciousness

Why psychologists are afraid of parties

Like any other tribe, scientists have their own hierarchy. The place of psychologists in this hierarchy is at the very bottom. I discovered this in my freshman year at university where I was studying science. We were told that college students would, for the first time, have the opportunity to study psychology in the first part of the science course. Encouraged by this news, I went to our group leader to ask him what he knew about this new opportunity. “Yes,” he replied. “But it never crossed my mind that one of my students would be so dumb as to want to study psychology.” He himself was a physicist.

Because, probably, that I was not quite sure what "stupid" meant, this remark did not stop me. I left physics and took up psychology. From then until now, I have continued to study psychology, but I have not forgotten my place in the scientific hierarchy. At parties where scientists gather, from time to time

Page 2 of 23

The question inevitably pops up: “What do you do?” - and I tend to think twice before answering, "I'm a psychologist."

Of course, much has changed in psychology in the last 30 years. We borrowed a lot of methods and concepts from other disciplines. We study not only behavior, but also the brain. We use computers to analyze our data and model mental processes. My university badge doesn't say "psychologist" but "cognitive neuroscientist."

Rice. item 1. General view and section of the human brain

Human brain, side view (top). The arrow marks the place where the cut shown in the bottom photo passed. The outer layer of the brain (cortex) consists of gray matter and forms many folds that allow you to fit a large surface area in a small volume. The cortex contains about 10 billion nerve cells.

And they ask me: “What do you do?” It seems to be the new head of the physics department. Unfortunately, my response “I am a cognitive neuroscientist” only delays the denouement. After my attempts to explain what, in fact, my work consists, she says: “Ah, so you are a psychologist!” - with that characteristic facial expression in which I read: “If only you could do real science!”.

A professor of English joins the conversation and raises the topic of psychoanalysis. She has a new student who "doesn't agree with Freud in many ways." In order not to spoil my evening, I refrain from suggesting that Freud was an inventor, and that his discussions about the human psyche are of little relevance to the case.

A few years ago, the editor of the British Journal of Psychiatry, apparently by mistake, asked me to write a review of a Freudian article. I was immediately struck by one subtle difference from the articles I usually review. As with any scientific article, there were many references to the literature. Basically, these are links to works on the same topic, published earlier. We refer to them partly in order to pay tribute to the achievements of their predecessors, but mainly in order to support certain statements that are contained in our own work. “You don't have to take my word for it. You can read a detailed rationale for the methods I used in Box and Cox (Box and Cox, 1964).” But the authors of this Freudian article did not at all try to back up the cited facts with references. References to the literature were not about facts, but about ideas. Using references, it was possible to trace the development of these ideas in the writings of various followers of Freud up to the original words of the teacher himself. At the same time, no facts were cited by which it would be possible to judge whether his ideas were fair.

“Freud may have had a great influence on literary criticism,” I tell the professor of English, “but he was not a real scientist. He was not interested in facts. I study psychology by scientific methods.”

“So,” she replies, “you are using a monster of machine intelligence to kill the human in us.”

On both sides of the abyss that separates our views, I hear the same thing: "Science cannot investigate consciousness." Why can't?

Exact and inexact sciences

In the system of scientific hierarchy, "exact" sciences occupy a high position, and "inexact" - low. The subjects studied by the exact sciences are like a cut diamond, which has a strictly defined shape, and all parameters can be measured with high accuracy. "Inexact" sciences study objects that look like an ice cream ball, the shape of which is far from being so definite, and the parameters can change from measurement to measurement. The exact sciences, such as physics and chemistry, study tangible objects that can be measured very accurately. For example, the speed of light (in a vacuum) is exactly 299,792,458 meters per second. A phosphorus atom weighs 31 times more than a hydrogen atom. These are very important numbers. Based on the atomic weight of various elements, it is possible to compile a periodic table, which once made it possible to draw the first conclusions about the structure of matter at the subatomic level.

Once biology was not such an exact science as physics and chemistry. This state of affairs changed dramatically after scientists discovered that genes consist of strictly defined sequences of nucleotides in DNA molecules. For example, the sheep prion gene consists of 960 nucleotides and begins like this:

I must admit that in the face of such precision and rigor, psychology looks like a very imprecise science. The most famous number in psychology is 7, the number of things that can be held in working memory at the same time. But even this figure needs to be clarified. George Miller's 1956 paper on this discovery was titled "The Magic Number Seven - Plus or Minus Two." Therefore, the best measurement result obtained by psychologists can vary in one direction or another by almost 30%. The number of items we can hold in working memory varies from time to time and from person to person. In a state of fatigue or anxiety, I will remember fewer numbers. I speak English and therefore can remember more numbers than those who speak Welsh. “What did you expect? says the professor of English. “The human soul cannot be straightened out like a butterfly in a shop window. Each of us is unique.”

This remark is not entirely appropriate. Of course, each of us is unique. But we all have common properties of the psyche. It is these fundamental properties that psychologists are looking for. Chemists had exactly the same problem with the substances they studied before the discovery of chemical

Page 3 of 23

elements in the 18th century. Each substance is unique. Psychology, compared to the "exact" sciences, had little time to find what to measure and figure out how to measure. Psychology as a scientific discipline has only existed for a little over 100 years. I am sure that in time psychologists will find what to measure and develop devices that will help us make these measurements very accurate.

Exact sciences are objective, inexact sciences are subjective

These optimistic words are based on my belief in the unstoppable progress of science. But, unfortunately, in the case of psychology, there are no solid grounds for such optimism. What we are trying to measure is qualitatively different from what is measured in the exact sciences.

In the exact sciences, the results of measurements are objective. They can be checked. “Don't believe that the speed of light is 299,792,458 meters per second? Here's your equipment. Measure yourself!” When we use this measurement equipment, the results will appear on dials, printouts and computer screens where anyone can read them. And psychologists use themselves or their volunteer assistants as measuring instruments. The results of such measurements are subjective. You can't check them.

Here is a simple psychological experiment. I run a program on my computer that shows a field of black dots continuously moving down from the top of the screen to the bottom. I stare at the screen for a minute or two. Then I press "Escape" and the dots stop moving. Objectively, they no longer move. If I put the tip of a pencil on one of them, I can make sure that this point is definitely not moving. But I still have a very strong subjective feeling that the dots are slowly moving up. If at that moment you were to enter my room, you would see fixed points on the screen. I would tell you that it seems to me that the dots are moving up, but how do you check this? After all, their movement occurs only in my head.

A real scientist wants to independently and independently verify the results of measurements reported by others. “Nullius in verba” is the motto of the Royal Society of London: “Do not believe what others tell you, no matter how high their authority may be.” If I followed this principle, I would have to agree that a scientific investigation of your inner world is impossible for me, because for this I have to rely on what you tell me about your inner experience.

For a while, psychologists pretended to be real scientists by only studying behavior—taking objective measurements of things like movements, button presses, reaction times. But behavioral research is by no means enough. Such studies leave out everything that is most interesting in our personal experience. We all know that our inner world is no less real than our life in the material world. Unrequited love brings no less suffering than a burn from touching a hot stove. The work of consciousness can influence the results of physical actions that can be objectively measured. For example, if you imagine that you are playing the piano, the quality of your performance may improve. So why shouldn't I take your word for it that you imagined playing the piano? Now we psychologists have returned to the study of subjective experience: sensations, memories, intentions. But the problem has not gone away: the mental phenomena that we study have a completely different status than the material phenomena that other scientists study. Only from your words can I learn about what is going on in your mind. You press a button to let me know you've seen a red light. Can you tell me what shade that red was. But there is no way I can get into your mind and check for myself how red was the light that you saw.

For my friend Rosalind, each number has a specific position in space, and each day of the week has its own color (see Fig. CV1 in the color inset). But maybe these are just metaphors? I have never experienced anything like it. Why should I believe her when she says that these are her immediate, uncontrollable sensations? Her sensations relate to the phenomena of the inner world, which I can not verify in any way.

Will big science help inexact science?

Exact science becomes "big science" when it starts using very expensive measuring instruments. The science of the brain went big when CT scanners were developed to scan the brain in the last quarter of the 20th century. One such scanner usually costs more than a million pounds. By sheer luck, being in the right place at the right time, I was able to use these devices when they first appeared, in the mid-eighties. The first such devices were based on the long-established principle of fluoroscopy. An x-ray machine can show bones inside your body because bones are much harder (dense) than skin and soft tissues. Similar density differences are observed in the brain. The skull surrounding the brain has a very high density, while the density of the tissues of the brain itself is much less. In the depths of the brain are cavities (ventricles) filled with fluid, they have the lowest density. A breakthrough in this field came with the development of axial computed tomography (ACT) technology and the construction of an ACT scanner. This machine uses X-rays to measure density, then solves a huge number of equations (which requires a powerful computer) and builds a three-dimensional image of the brain (or any other part of the body) reflecting differences in density. Such a device for the first time made it possible to see the internal structure of the brain of a living person - a voluntary participant in the experiment.

A few years later, another method was developed, even better than the previous one - magnetic resonance imaging (MRI). MRI does not use X-rays, but radio waves and a very strong magnetic field. Unlike fluoroscopy, this procedure is not at all dangerous to health. An MRI scanner is much more sensitive to density differences than an ACT scanner. On images of the brain of a living person, obtained with its help, different types of tissues are distinguishable. The quality of such images is not lower than the quality of photographs of the brain, after death, removed from the skull, preserved with chemicals and cut into thin layers.

Rice. item 2. An example of an MRI structural image of the brain and a section of the brain removed from a corpse

Above is a photograph of one of the sections of the brain, removed from the skull after death and cut into thin layers. Below is an image of one of the layers of the brain of a living person, obtained by magnetic resonance imaging (MRI).

Structural tomography of the brain has played a huge role in the development of medicine. Brain injuries from road traffic accidents, strokes, or tumor growth can have a profound effect on behavior. They can lead to severe memory loss or serious personality changes. Before the advent of CT scanners, the only way to find out exactly where an injury occurred was to remove the skull cap and look. Usually this was done after death, but sometimes in a living patient - when a neurosurgical operation was required. Now tomographs allow you to accurately determine the location of the injury. All that is required of the patient is to lie motionless inside the tomograph for 15 minutes.

Rice. item 3. An example of an MRI scan showing brain damage

This patient suffered two strokes in a row, as a result of which the auditory cortex of the right and left hemispheres was destroyed. The injury is clearly visible on the MRI image.

Structural tomography of the brain is both an exact and a big science. Measurements of the structural parameters of the brain, carried out using these methods, can be very accurate and objective. But what do these measurements have to do with the problem of psychology as an "inexact" science?

Measurement of brain activity

It was not structural tomography that helped solve the problem. Progress in this area was provided by functional tomographs, developed a few years after structural ones. These devices allow you to record the energy consumption of brain tissues. Whether we are awake or asleep, the 15 billion nerve cells (neurons) in our brain are constantly sending signals to each other. This consumes a lot of energy. Our brain consumes about 20% of the energy of the entire body, despite the fact that its mass is only about 2% of body weight. The entire brain is permeated with a network of blood vessels, through which energy is transferred in the form of oxygen contained in the blood. The distribution of energy in the brain is very finely tuned, so that more of it flows into those parts of the brain that are most active at the moment. When we use our hearing, the most active parts of our brain are the two lateral regions, which contain neurons that receive signals directly from the ears (see Figure CV2 in the color inset). When the neurons in these areas are active, more blood flows there. This connection between brain activity and local changes in blood flow has been known to physiologists for more than 100 years, but before the invention of functional tomographs, it was not possible to record such changes. Functional brain imaging scanners (developed on the basis of positron emission tomography (PET) and functional magnetic resonance imaging fMRI) allow you to register such changes in blood supply, indicating which areas of the brain are currently most active.

The biggest disadvantage of such tomographs is the inconvenience that a person experiences when scanning his brain. He has to lie on his back for about an hour, as still as possible. The only thing you can do while inside the scanner is to think, but in the case of fMRI, even thinking is not so easy, because the scanner makes such a noise, as if a jackhammer is working right under your ear. In one of the earliest, groundbreaking studies, using an early model of a positron emission tomograph, subjects were asked to imagine that they were leaving their home and walking through the streets, turning left at every intersection. It turned out that such purely imaginary actions are quite enough to cause the activation of many parts of the brain.

Rice. item 4. The cerebral cortex and its cells

Section of the cerebral cortex under a microscope and layers of nervous tissue visible on the section.

This is where big science comes to the rescue of "inaccurate" psychology. The subject, lying in the tomograph, imagines that he is walking down the street. In fact, he does not move and does not see anything. These events occur only in his head. There is no way I can get into his mind to check if he is really doing what he was asked to do. But with the CT scanner, I can get into his brain. And I can see that when he imagines walking down the street and turning left, there is activity in his brain of a certain kind.

Of course, most tomographic studies of the brain are more objective. For example, a red light is lit in front of the subject's eyes, and he presses buttons, while actually moving his fingers. But I (like some of my colleagues) have always been more interested in the side of the brain, associated with purely mental phenomena. We found that when a subject imagines that he is pressing a button, the same areas in his brain are activated that are activated when he actually presses it. If not for the tomograph, we would have absolutely no objective signs by which we could say that the subject imagines that he is pressing the button. We can make sure that there is not the slightest movement of the fingers or muscle contractions. Therefore, we believe that he is following our instruction to imagine that he is pressing a button every time he hears a certain signal. By measuring brain activity, we get objective confirmation of this mental phenomenon. Using a functional CT scanner, I could probably tell if you imagine moving your foot or finger. But as of now, I probably won't be able to tell which finger you were thinking about.

Rice. item 5. Parts of the brain and areas of the cortex

Shown at the top are the main parts of the brain. At the bottom, areas (“fields”) of the cerebral cortex according to Brodmann are shown (the cerebellum and brain stem are removed). Brodmann fields are highlighted on the basis appearance sections of the cortex under a microscope. The numbers assigned to these fields are arbitrary.

Perhaps I should not have done this, but the study of vision. Nancy Canwisher and her group at Massachusetts Institute of Technology showed that when we look at a face (anyone), a certain part of the brain is always activated in our brain, and when we look at a house (any one), another part of the brain located nearby is activated. If you ask the subject to imagine a person or building taken away a few seconds ago, the corresponding areas in his brain are activated. When I lie inside a scanner in Dr. Canwisher's lab, she can tell what I'm thinking (if I'm thinking only of faces or only of houses).

Rice. item 6. Subject lying inside a CT scanner for brain scanning

This solves the problem of psychology as an "inexact" science. Now we have no need to worry about the inaccuracy, the subjectivity of our information about mental phenomena. Instead, we can make accurate, objective measurements of brain activity. Probably, now I will not be ashamed to admit that I am a psychologist.

But back to our party. I can't resist telling everyone about the big science of brain imaging. The head of the physics department likes this one new stage in the development of psychology. After all, it was physics that made it possible. But the English professor is not ready to accept that the study of brain activity can tell us something about the human psyche.

Rice. item 7. Brain scan results during real and imaginary movements

The diagrams above show the brain slices (top and middle) showing brain activity. The upper slices show the activity observed when the subject moves his right hand, and the lower slices show the activity observed when the subject only imagines that he is moving his right hand.

Rice. item 8. Faces and houses, visible and imagined

The brain (view from below), and its areas associated with the perception of persons and places. The activity of the same area increases both when we see a face and when we only imagine a face. The same applies to the area related to the perception of places.

“Once you thought that we had a camera in our heads. Now you think that there is a computer. Even if you manage to look inside this computer, you will still be left with the same battered model. Of course, computers are smarter than cameras. Maybe they are able to recognize faces or collect eggs on a chicken farm with mechanical hands. But they will never be able to generate new ideas and transfer them to other computers. They will never create a computer culture. Such things are beyond the power of the machine mind.”

I'm leaving to fill my glass. I don't get into an argument. I am not a philosopher. I do not hope to convince others that I am right by the force of arguments. I accept only those arguments that are based on practical experience. And I undertake to show how to make the impossible possible.

How can psychic phenomena arise from material phenomena?

Of course, it would be foolish to think that one can limit oneself to measuring brain activity and forget about the psyche. Brain activity can serve as an indicator of mental activity and thus gives us an objective marker of subjective mental experience. But brain activity and mental experience are not the same thing. With the right equipment, I could probably find a neuron in my brain that fires only when I see blue color. But, as the professor of English will remind me with pleasure, this activity and the color blue are not the same thing. Tomographic studies of the brain clearly show us the seemingly insurmountable gulf between objective physical matter and subjective psychic experience.

Exact sciences deal with material objects that can directly affect our senses. We see the light. We feel the weight of a piece of iron. Engaging in exact sciences, such as physics, often requires scientists to work hard physically with the materials under study. The best example of such a scientist is Marie Curie, who is said to have had to process several tons of uranium ore to isolate one-tenth of a gram of radium. This

Page 6 of 23

hard physical labor and made it possible to understand the phenomenon of radioactivity, to find medical applications for X-rays, and ultimately to design a computer tomograph. In doing so, of course, we are assisted by special equipment designed to make fine measurements, working with very rare elements such as radium, very small objects, such as nucleotides in a DNA molecule, or very fast processes, such as the propagation of light. But all this special equipment, like magnifying glasses, only artificially enhances the capabilities of our senses. It helps us see what really exists. No such device will allow us to see what is happening in the inner world of another person. The objects of the inner world do not really exist.

And finally at this party there is a meeting that I was most afraid of. This time I am approached by a self-confident young man without a tie, who is probably engaged in molecular genetics.

He is probably smart man. How can he say such nonsense? He's just mocking me.

It was only very recently that I managed to realize that it was my own stupidity that did not understand him. Of course, I can read other people's minds. And this is available not only to psychologists. We all read each other's minds all the time. Without it, we would not be able to exchange ideas, we would not be able to create a culture! But how does our brain allow us to penetrate into the inner worlds hidden in the minds of other people?

I can look into the depths of the universe with a telescope and observe the activity inside your brain with a tomograph, but I cannot penetrate your consciousness. We all believe that our inner world is not at all the same as the real material world that surrounds us.

And yet in Everyday life we are as interested in the thoughts of other people as we are in the objects of the material world. We interact with other people by exchanging thoughts with them, much more than we physically interact with their bodies. By reading this book, you will know my thoughts. And I, in turn, write it in the hope that it will allow me to change the way you think.

How the brain creates our inner world

So, this is the problem of psychologists? Are we trying to explore the inner world of other people and the phenomena of the psyche, while "real" science is concerned with the material world? The material world is qualitatively different from the world of our psyche. The sense organs allow us to make direct contact with the material world. And our inner world belongs only to us. How can another person explore such a world?

In this book, I am going to show that there really is no difference between the inner world of man and the material world. The difference between them is an illusion created by our brain. Everything that we know, both about the material world and about the inner world of other people, we know thanks to the brain. But the connection of our brain with the material world of physical bodies is just as indirect as its connection with the non-material world of ideas. Hiding from us all the unconscious conclusions to which it comes, our brain creates in us the illusion of direct contact with the material world. At the same time, it gives us the illusion that our inner world is separate and belongs only to us. These two illusions give us the feeling that in the world we live in, we are acting as independent agents. At the same time, we can share our experience of perceiving the world around us with other people. Over the millennia, this ability to share experiences has created human culture, which in turn can influence how our brains work.

By overcoming these illusions created by the brain, we can lay the foundation for a science that will explain to us how the brain shapes our consciousness.

“Don't expect me to take your word for it,” says the professor of English. “Give me proof.”

And I promise her that everything I talk about in this book will be convincingly proven by rigorous experimental data. If you would like to review these data yourself, you will find a detailed list of links to all primary sources at the end of the book.

Part one

What is behind the illusions of our brain

1. What a damaged brain can tell us

Perception of the material world

When I was at school, chemistry was given to me worse than all subjects. The only scientific fact I remember from chemistry class is about one trick that can be used in practice. You are given many small containers of white powders, and you must determine which substance is which. Taste them. The sweet tasting substance would be lead acetate. Just don't try too much!

This approach to chemistry is common to many ordinary people. It is usually applied to the contents of those jars that are in the depths of the kitchen cabinet. If you can't tell what it is by looking at it, try it. This is how we get to know the material world. We explore it with our senses.

Rice. 1.1. The retina of the eye, which provides the link between light and brain activity

The retina, located deep in the eye, contains a large number of special neurons (photoreceptors) whose activity changes when light falls on them. Cone photoreceptors are located in the middle of the retina (in the fovea region). There are three types of cones, each of which responds to light of a specific wavelength (red, green, and blue). Around the fovea are photoreceptor rods that react to weak light of any color. All these cells send signals along the optic nerve to the visual cortex.

It follows that if our sense organs are damaged, it is bad for our ability to explore the material world. It is likely that you are nearsighted. If I ask you to take off your glasses and look around, you will not be able to distinguish small objects located just a couple of meters away from you. There is nothing surprising here. It is our sense organs - eyes, ears, tongue and others - that provide a connection between the material world and our consciousness. Our eyes and ears, like a video camera, collect information about the material world and transmit it to consciousness. If the eyes or ears are damaged, this information cannot be transmitted properly. Such damage makes it difficult for us to get to know the outside world.

This problem

Page 7 of 23

becomes even more interesting if we consider how information from the eyes reaches consciousness. Let's forget for a moment the question of how the electrical activity of the eye's photoreceptors translates into our sense of color, and confine ourselves to observing that information from the eyes (as well as ears, tongue, and other senses) enters the brain. It follows that brain damage can also make it difficult to get to know the material world.

Mind and brain

Before we begin to understand how brain damage can affect our perception of the world around us, we need to take a closer look at the connection between our psyche and the brain. This connection must be close. As we learned in the prologue, whenever we imagine a face, a special area in our brain associated with the perception of faces is activated. In this case, knowing about a purely mental experience, we can predict which area of ​​the brain will be activated in this case. As we will soon see, brain injuries can have a profound effect on the psyche. Moreover, knowing exactly where the brain was injured, we can predict how the patient's psyche has changed as a result of this. But this connection between the brain and the psyche is imperfect. This is not a one-to-one relationship. Some changes in brain activity may not affect the psyche in any way.

On the other hand, I am deeply convinced that any changes in the psyche are associated with changes in brain activity. I am convinced of this because I believe that everything that happens in my inner world ( mental activity) is caused by, or at least dependent on, brain activity.

So, if I'm right in my belief, the sequence of events should look something like this. Light hits the light-sensitive cells (photoreceptors) in our eyes, and they send signals to the brain. The mechanism of this phenomenon is already well known. Then, the activity that occurs in the brain somehow creates a sense of color and shape in our mind. The mechanism of this phenomenon is still completely unknown. But whatever it is, we can conclude that in our minds there can be no knowledge about the world around us that is not represented in the brain in any way. Everything we know about the world, we know thanks to the brain. Therefore, we probably do not need to ask the question: “how do we or our consciousness cognize the world around us? Instead, you need to ask yourself: how does our brain learn about the world around us? By asking about the brain rather than consciousness, we can put aside for a while the question of how knowledge about the world around us gets into our consciousness. Unfortunately this trick doesn't work. To find out what your brain knows about the world around you, I would first ask you the question: “What do you see?” I appeal to your consciousness to find out what is displayed in your brain. As we will see, this method is not always reliable.

When the brain doesn't know

Of all the sensory systems in the brain, we know the most about the visual system. The visible picture of the world is first displayed in neurons located deep in the retina. The resulting image is inverted and mirrored, just like the picture that appears inside a camera: the neurons located on the retina at the upper left represent the lower right part of the visual field. The retina sends signals to the primary visual cortex (V1) in the back of the brain through the thalamus (thalamus), a kind of relay station located deep in the brain. The neurons that transmit these signals partially cross over, so that the left side of each eye is displayed in the right hemisphere, and the right side in the left. The "photographic" image in the primary visual cortex is preserved, so that the neurons located in the upper part of the visual cortex of the left hemisphere? display the lower right part of the field of view.

The consequences of damage to the primary visual cortex depend on where exactly the injury occurred. If the upper left part of the visual cortex is damaged, then the patient is unable to see objects located in the lower right part of the visual field. In this part of the visual field, such patients are blind.

Some migraine sufferers occasionally lose sight of part of their visual field because they temporarily lose blood flow to their visual cortex. This symptom usually begins with a small “blind” area in the visual field, which gradually

Page 8 of 23

grows. This area is often surrounded by a shimmering zigzag line called the fortification spectrum.

Rice. 1.2. How signals are transmitted along the nerves from the retina to the visual cortex

The light signal from the left side of the visual field enters the right hemisphere. The brain is shown below.

Before information from the primary visual cortex is passed on to the brain for the next processing step, the resulting image is decomposed into components such as information about shape, color, and movement. These components of visual information are transmitted further to different parts of the brain. In rare cases, brain injuries can affect areas of the brain involved in the processing of only one of these components, while the rest of the areas remain intact. If the area associated with the perception of color (V4) is damaged, a person sees the world as colorless (this syndrome is called achromatopsia, or color blindness). We have all seen black and white films and photographs, so it is not so difficult to imagine the feelings of people suffering from this syndrome. It is much more difficult to imagine the world of a person who has a damaged area associated with the visual perception of movement (V5). Over time, visible objects, such as cars, change their position in the field of view - but at the same time, it does not seem to the person that they are moving (this syndrome is called akinetopsia). This sensation is probably the opposite of the waterfall illusion I mentioned in the prologue. In this illusion, which each of us can experience, objects do not change their position in the field of view, but it seems to us that they are moving.

Rice. 1.3. How damage to the visual cortex affects perception

Damage to the visual cortex causes blindness in certain parts of the visual field. Loss of the entire visual cortex of the right hemisphere causes blindness on the entire left side of the visual field (hemiopia). Loss of a small area in the lower half of the visual cortex of the right hemisphere leads to the appearance of a blind spot in the upper left half of the visual field (scotoma). Loss of the entire lower half of the visual cortex of the right hemisphere causes blindness in the entire upper half of the left side of the visual field (quadrant hemianopia).

Rice. 1.4. Blind spot development in migraine according to Carl Lashley

The symptom begins with the fact that a blind spot appears in the middle of the visual field, which then gradually increases in size.

At the next stage of processing visual information, its components, such as information about the shape and color, are again combined to recognize objects in the field of view. The areas of the brain where this happens are sometimes damaged, while the areas where the previous stages of visual processing take place remain intact. People with these injuries may have trouble recognizing visible objects. They are able to see and describe the various characteristics of an object, but do not understand what it is. This impairment of recognition is called agnosia. With this syndrome, the primary visual information continues to enter the brain, but the person can no longer comprehend it. In one of the varieties of this syndrome, people are not able to recognize faces (this is prosopagnosia, or agnosia for faces). A person understands that he sees a face in front of him, but cannot understand whose it is. In such people, the area associated with the perception of faces, which I talked about in the prologue, is damaged.

Everything seems to be clear with these observations. Brain damage makes it difficult to transmit information about the world that is collected by the senses. The nature of the impact of these damages on our ability to cognize the world around us is determined by the stage of information transfer at which the damage affects. But sometimes our brain can play weird tricks on us.

When the brain knows but doesn't want to say

The dream of every neurophysiologist is to find a person who would have such an unusual view of the world that we would have to radically reconsider our ideas about how the brain works. To find such a person, two things are needed. First, you need luck to meet him (or her). Secondly, we need to be smart enough to understand the importance of what we observe.

“Of course, you always had enough luck and intelligence,” says the professor of English.

Unfortunately no. Once I was very lucky, but I was not smart enough to understand it. As a young man, when I worked at the Institute of Psychiatry in south London, I explored the human mechanisms of learning. I was introduced to a man who suffered from severe memory loss. For a week, he came to my laboratory every day and learned to perform one task that required a certain motor skill. His result gradually improved without deviations from the norm, and the developed skill was retained by him even after a week's break. But at the same time, he had such a severe memory loss that every day he said that he had never met me before and had never performed this task. “How strange,” I thought. But I was interested in the problems of teaching motor skills. This person learned the required skill normally and did not arouse my interest. Of course, many other researchers have been able to appreciate the importance of people with similar symptoms. Such people may not remember anything about what happened to them earlier, even if it was only yesterday. Previously, we assumed that this is due to the fact that the events that occurred are not recorded in the person's brain. But for the person I worked with, the experience clearly had a long-term effect on the brain, because he was able to perform the task more and more successfully day by day. But these long-term changes taking place in the brain did not affect his consciousness. He couldn't remember anything that happened to him yesterday. The existence of such people indicates that our brain may know something about the world around us that is unknown to our consciousness.

Mel Goodale and David Milner did not repeat my mistake when they met the woman known by the initials D.F. They immediately realized the importance of what they were able to observe. D.F. suffered carbon monoxide poisoning from a malfunctioning water heater. This poisoning damaged the part of her brain's visual system associated with the perception of form. She could vaguely perceive light, shadow, and color, but she could not recognize objects because she could not see what shape they were. Goodale and Milner noticed that D.F. seemed to be much better at walking and picking up items around the test site than one would expect, given her near-total blindness. For several years, they conducted a number of experiments with her participation. These experiments confirmed the presence

Page 9 of 23

discrepancies between what she could see and what she could do.

One of the experiments done by Goodale and Milner looked like this. The experimenter held a stick in his hand and asked D.F. how the stick was positioned. She couldn't tell if the wand was horizontal or vertical or at some angle. It seemed that she did not see the wand at all and was just trying to guess its location. The experimenter then asked her to reach out and take hold of the stick with her hand. It worked out fine for her. At the same time, she turned her hand in advance so that it was more convenient to take the wand. At whatever angle the wand was placed, she could grab it with her hand without any problems. This observation shows that the brain of D.F. “knows” at what angle the wand is located, and can use this information by controlling the movements of her hand. But D.F. cannot use this information to recognize where the wand is located. Her brain knows something about the world around her that her consciousness does not know.

Rice. 1.5. Unconscious actions

Patient D.F. the part of the brain needed to recognize objects is damaged, while the part of the brain needed to hold objects in the hand remains intact. She does not understand how the “letter” is rotated relative to the slot. But she can turn it the way she wants by pushing it through the slot.

Very few people are known to have exactly the same symptoms as D.F. But there are quite a few people with brain damage in which the brain plays similar jokes. Perhaps the most striking discrepancy occurs in people with blindsight syndrome, which is caused by trauma to the primary visual cortex. As we already know, such injuries lead to the fact that a person ceases to see any part of the visual field. Lawrence Weiskrantz was the first to show that in some people this blind area of ​​the visual field is not completely blind. In one of his experiments, a light spot moves in front of the subject's eyes in the blind part of his field of vision to the right or left, and the subject is asked to say what? He sees. This question strikes him as extraordinarily stupid. He doesn't see anything. Then, instead, he is asked to guess which way the spot moved, to the left or to the right. This question also strikes him as rather stupid, but he is willing to believe that the venerable Oxford professor knows what he is doing. Professor Weiskrantz found that some people are much better at guessing the direction of the spot than if they were just guessing. In one such experiment, the subject answered correctly more than 80% of the time, although he continued to claim that he did not see anything. Thus, if I had a blindsight syndrome, consciousness could tell me that I do not see anything, while my brain would have some information about the visible world around me and somehow prompt me, helping me “guess” the correct answer . What is this knowledge that my brain has, but I don't?

When the brain is lying

The unknown knowledge of a person with a blindsight syndrome is at least true. But sometimes brain injuries lead to the fact that consciousness receives information about the world around us, which in reality does not correspond at all. A deaf old woman was awakened in the middle of the night by the sound of loud music. She searched the entire apartment looking for the source of these sounds, but she couldn't find it anywhere. She eventually realized that the music was only in her head. Since then, she has almost always heard this non-existent music. Sometimes it was a baritone accompanied by a guitar, and sometimes a choir accompanied by a whole orchestra.

Rice. 1.6. Spontaneous brain activity associated with blindness (Charles Bonnet syndrome) causes visual hallucinations

The nature of these hallucinations depends on which part of the brain is active. The brain is shown below.

Distinct auditory and visual hallucinations occur in about 10% of elderly people suffering from severe forms of hearing or vision loss. Visual hallucinations that occur with Charles Bonnet syndrome are often only multi-colored spots or patterns. People suffering from this syndrome see the finest nets of gold wire, ovals filled with brickwork-like patterns, or fireworks of brightly colored explosions. Sometimes hallucinations take the form of human faces or figures. These faces are usually crooked and ugly, with protruding eyes and teeth. The figures of people described by patients are usually small, wearing hats or costumes from a certain era.

The heads of men and women of the 17th century are visible, with pleasant thick hair. Probably wigs. Everyone looks extremely disapproving. Never smile.

Dominique Ffitch and his colleagues at the Institute of Psychiatry scanned the brains of people suffering from Charles Bonnet syndrome during such hallucinations. Immediately before a person saw someone's faces in front of him, the activity of the area associated with the perception of faces began to increase in him. Similarly, activity in the area associated with the perception of color began to increase just before the subject reported seeing a color spot.

How Brain Activity Creates False Knowledge

Currently, there are already quite a few studies demonstrating that brain activity can create a false experience regarding events taking place in the outside world. One example of such an experience is related to epilepsy. For every 200 people, on average, there is one who suffers from epilepsy. This disease is associated with a disorder of the brain, as a result of which the electrical activity of a large number of neurons gets out of control from time to time, causing a seizure (seizure). In many cases, the development of a seizure is caused by the activation of a certain part of the brain, in which sometimes a small damaged area can be identified. Uncontrolled activation of neurons begins in this area, and then spreads throughout the brain.

Just before a seizure, many epileptics begin to experience a strange sensation known as an "aura." Epileptics quickly remember what form their aura takes, and when this condition occurs, they know that a seizure will soon begin. Different epileptics experience different sensations. For one, it may be the smell of burnt rubber. For others, it's ringing in the ears. The nature of these sensations depends on the location of the area from which the seizure begins.

Approximately 5% of epileptics have a seizure in the visual cortex. Just before the attack, they see simple multi-colored figures, sometimes rotating or sparkling. We can get some idea of ​​what these sensations are like from sketches made by epileptics after a seizure (see Fig. CV3 in color).

Page 10 of 23

insert).

One patient, Katherine Mize, described in detail complex visual hallucinations that she had associated with flu-induced seizures. She experienced hallucinations for weeks after these seizures stopped.

When I closed my eyes during a lecture, shimmering red lights appeared in front of me against a black background. geometric figures. At first I was scared, but it was so exciting that I kept looking at them in complete amazement. Fantastic images appeared before my closed eyes. Indistinct circles and rectangles merged to form beautiful symmetrical geometric shapes. These figures constantly grew, again and again absorbed each other and grew again. I remember something like an explosion of black dots on the right side of the visual field. These dots, set against a glowing red background, gracefully spread outward from their point of origin. Two flat red rectangles appeared and moved in different directions. A red ball on a stick moved in circles around these rectangles.

Then a flickering and running red wave appeared at the bottom of the field of vision.

Some epileptics have a seizure in the auditory cortex, and before it starts, they hear sounds and voices.

Sometimes during the aura, epileptics experience complex sensations, during which they relive the events of the past:

A girl who had seizures at the age of eleven. [At the beginning of the seizure] sees herself at the age of seven, walking through a grassy field. Suddenly it seems to her that someone is going to attack her from behind and begin to choke her, or hit her on the head, and she is seized with fear. This episode was repeated almost unchanged before each attack and was apparently based on real event[which happened to her at the age of seven].

These observations suggest that the abnormal neural activity associated with epileptic seizures may lead to a false knowledge of the world around the person. But in order to verify the validity of this conclusion, it is necessary to conduct an appropriate experiment, during which we will control the nervous activity of the brain by directly stimulating its cells.

In some severe forms of epilepsy, the only way to get rid of seizures is to cut out the damaged part of the brain. Before cutting this area, the neurosurgeon must make sure that its removal will not affect any vital function, such as speech. The great Canadian neurosurgeon Wilder Penfield was the first to perform such operations, during which the patient's brain was stimulated with electrical discharges in order to get an idea of ​​​​the functions of its individual sections. This is done by applying an electrode to the surface of the exposed brain and passing a very weak electrical current through the brain, which causes the activation of neurons located close to the electrode. This procedure is completely painless and can be performed when the patient is fully conscious.

Rice. 1.7. Direct brain stimulation causes the illusion of real sensations

Above is a photograph of a patient prepared for surgery; an incision line is marked above the left ear.

Below is the surface of the brain with numbered labels that mark areas of positive responses to stimulation.

Patients whose brains are stimulated in this way report sensations similar to those experienced before an epileptic seizure. The nature of these sensations depends on which part of the brain is being stimulated at the moment.

Patient 21: “Wait a minute. Looks like the figure on the left. Seems to be male or female. I think it was a woman. She didn't seem to be wearing any clothes. She seemed to be dragging something or running after the van.”

Patient 13: "They're saying something, but I can't make out what it is." When stimulating the neighboring area, he said: “Here, it starts again. It's water, it sounds like a toilet flush or a dog barking. First the sound of the drain, and then the dog barked.” When stimulating the third, neighboring area, he said: “I think I have music in my ears. A girl or a woman sings, but I don't know the tune. It came from a tape recorder or from a receiver.”

Patient 15: When the electrode was applied, she said, “I feel like a lot of people are yelling at me.” After stimulating the neighboring area, she said: “Oh, everyone is yelling at me, let them stop!” She explained: “They were yelling at me for doing something wrong, everyone was yelling.”

These observations confirm that we can create false knowledge about the world around us by directly stimulating certain areas of the brain. But all of these patients had brain damage. Will the same be observed in healthy people?

How to make our brain deceive us

Do not stick electrodes into the human brain unless absolutely necessary. However, at all times and in all cultures, many people have felt the need to stimulate their brain with various substances. During such stimulations, our brain informs us not about the “real” world around us, but about some other world, which, according to many, is better than ours. Like any other student in the sixties, I read Aldous Huxley's book on hallucinogenic drugs, The Doors of Perception. Perhaps my fascination with this book led me to devote much of my subsequent scientific activity studying hallucinations?

Describing the action of mescaline, Huxley wrote: "That's how you should see what things really are." When he closed his eyes, his field of vision was filled with “brightly colored, constantly

Page 11 of 23

changing structures. Huxley also quotes Weir Mitchell's more detailed description of the action of mescaline:

Upon entering this world, he saw many "stellar points" and what looked like "shards of colored glass." Then there were “gentle floating films of color”. They were replaced by a “harsh rush of countless dots of white light” that swept across the field of view. Then came zigzag lines of bright colors, which somehow turned into swollen clouds of even brighter hues. There were buildings, then landscapes. There was a gothic tower of bizarre construction, with dilapidated statues in doorways or on stone pillars. “As I watched, every protruding corner, cornice, and even the faces of the stones at the joints began to gradually be covered or humiliated by clusters of what seemed to be huge gems, but the stones were unworked, so that some looked like masses of transparent fruits ...”

The action of LSD can be very similar.

Now, little by little, I began to enjoy the unprecedented colors and play of shapes that continued to exist before my closed eyes. A kaleidoscope of fantastic images washed over me; alternating, motley, they diverged and converged in circles and spirals, exploded in fountains of color, mixed and turned into each other in a continuous stream.

When the eyes are open, the face of the “real” world is strangely altered.

The world around me is now even more terrifyingly transformed. Everything in the room was spinning, and familiar things and pieces of furniture took on a grotesque menacing shape. They were all in constant motion, as if possessed by inner restlessness.

Rice. 1.8. Effects that psychotropic drugs may have on visual experience

I saw that various folds and waves were moving all over the surface of my blanket, as if snakes were crawling under it. I couldn't follow the individual waves, but I could clearly see them moving across the blanket. Suddenly, all these waves began to gather together in one section of the blanket.

Verification of experience for compliance with reality

I must conclude that if my brain is damaged or disturbed by electrical stimulation or psychotropic drugs, then I should be very careful in trusting the information that my consciousness receives about the world around me. Some of this information will no longer be available to me. Some will receive my brain, but I will not know anything about it. Even worse, some of the information I receive may turn out to be false and have nothing to do with the real-life material world.

When faced with such a problem, my main task should be to learn to distinguish between true sensations and false ones. Sometimes it's simple. If I see something when my eyes are closed, then these are visions, and not components of the material world. If I hear voices when I'm alone in a room with good soundproofing, then these voices are most likely only in my head. I must not trust such sensations, because I know that my senses need to contact the outside world in order to collect information about it.

Sometimes I can understand that I should not trust my feelings if they are too fantastic to be true. If I see a woman a few inches tall, dressed in a 17th century dress and pushing a baby carriage, it is clearly a hallucination. If I see hedgehogs and some small brown rodents walking on the ceiling above my head, I understand that this is a hallucination. I understand that I should not believe such sensations, because in the real world this does not happen.

But how do I know that my feelings are false if they are perfectly plausible? That deaf old woman, who first heard loud music, at first thought that the music was really coming from somewhere, and looked for its source in her apartment. Only after she could not find anything did she come to the conclusion that this music sounds only in her head. If she lived in an apartment with thin walls and suffered from noisy neighbors, she might conclude, and quite logically, that they turned the radio back on full volume.

How do we know what is real and what is not?

Sometimes a person can be absolutely sure of the reality of their sensations, which are actually false.

A great many terrible and frightening visions and voices haunted me, and although (in my opinion) they had no reality in themselves, yet they seemed to me to be so and made exactly the same impression on me as if they really were what they seemed to be. .

The passage quoted is taken from The Life of the Rev. Mr. George Tross. This book was written by George Tross himself and published by his order in 1714, shortly after his death. The impressions described were experienced by him much earlier, when he was 20 years old. small years. Remembering them later, Mr. Tross understood that these voices did not really exist, but at the time when he suffered from this illness, he was completely sure of their reality.

I heard a voice, I thought, right behind me, saying More Humility... More Humility... quite a long time. In agreement with him, then I took off my stockings, then my trousers, then my camisole, and while I was undressing like this, I had a strong inner feeling that I was doing everything right and in full accordance with the intention of the voice.

Today, a person who talks about such experiences would be diagnosed with schizophrenia. We still have not been able to figure out what the cause of this disease is. But what is striking is that schizophrenics, experiencing such false sensations, firmly believe in their reality. They go to great lengths of intellectual effort to explain how such apparently impossible things

Page 12 of 23

may actually exist.

In the 40s of the XX century, Percy King was sure that he was being pursued on the streets of New York by a group of young people.

I couldn't see them anywhere. I heard one of them, a woman, say: “You can’t get away from us: we will watch for you and sooner or later we will get to you!” The riddle was aggravated by the fact that one of these "persecutors" repeated my thoughts aloud verbatim. I tried to get away from them like before, but this time I tried to do it with the subway, running in and out of stations, jumping in and out of trains, until 1:00 am. But at every station where I got off the train, I heard their voices closer than ever. I wondered: how could so many pursuers chase me so quickly without being seen by me?

Not believing in either the devil or God, King found an explanation for his experience related to modern technology.

Maybe they were ghosts? Or is it that I developed the ability of a medium? Not! Among these persecutors, as I later gradually discovered by deduction, were evidently several brothers and sisters who had inherited from one of their parents some amazing, unprecedented, absolutely unthinkable occult abilities. Believe it or not, some of them not only could read other people's minds, but they could also transmit their magnetic voices - commonly referred to here as "radio voices" - for several miles without raising their voices or making any noticeable effort, and their voices sounded at this distance as if they were heard from the headphones of a radio receiver, and this was done without the use of electrical devices. This unique occult ability to transmit their "radio voices" over such long distances seems to be provided by their natural, bodily electricity, of which they have many times more than normal people. Perhaps the iron in their red blood cells is magnetized. The vibrations of their vocal cords apparently generate wireless waves, and these vocal radio waves are picked up by the human ear without being rectified. As a result, combined with their telepathic abilities, they are able to carry on a conversation with another person's unspoken thoughts and then, through so-called "radio voices", respond to those thoughts aloud so that that person can hear them. These persecutors are also capable of transmitting their magnetic voices through plumbing pipes, using them as electrical conductors, speaking while clinging to the pipe, so that it seems as if the speaker's voice is coming from the water flowing from the faucet connected to this pipe. One of them is able to make his voice rumble through large water mains for miles - a truly amazing phenomenon. Most people are hesitant to talk about such things to their accomplices, lest they be mistaken for lunatics.

Unfortunately, King himself was not ready to follow his own advice. He knew that "people who have auditory hallucinations hear imaginary things." But he was convinced that the voices he himself heard were real and not the product of hallucinations. He believed that he had discovered “the greatest observed psychological phenomena” and told others about it. But for all the ingenuity with which he explained the reality of these voices, he failed to convince the psychiatrists that he was right. He was kept in a psychiatric hospital.

King and many people like him are convinced that their feelings do not deceive them. If what they feel seems incredible or impossible, they are ready to change their ideas about the world around them rather than deny reality to their sensations.

But the hallucinations associated with schizophrenia have one very interesting feature. These are not just false sensations concerning the material world. Schizophrenics don't just see some colors and hear some sounds. Their hallucinations themselves relate to the phenomena of the psyche. They hear voices that comment on their actions, give advice and give orders. Our brains are capable of forming false inner worlds of other people.

So, if something happens to my brain, my perception of the world can no longer be taken at face value. The brain can create distinct sensations that have nothing to do with reality. These sensations reflect things that do not exist, but one can be quite sure that they exist.

“Yes, but my brain is fine,” says the English professor. “I know what is true and what is not.”

This chapter shows that a damaged brain not only makes it difficult to perceive the world around us. It can also create a sense of perception of something that is not really there. But we should not turn up our noses either. As we will see in the next chapter, even if our brain is healthy and working perfectly, it can still tell us lies about the world around us.

2. What a healthy brain tells us about the world

Even if all our senses are in order and the brain is working normally, we still do not have direct access to the material world. It may seem to us that we directly perceive the world around us, but this is an illusion created by our brain.

Illusion of completeness of perception

Imagine that I blindfolded you and led you into an unfamiliar room. Then I remove the bandage from your eyes, and you look around. Even in that unusual case, if there is an elephant in one corner of the room and a sewing machine in the other, you will immediately get an idea of ​​\u200b\u200bwhat is in this room. You don't have to think or make any effort to get this idea.

In the first half of the 19th century, the human ability to easily and quickly perceive the world around us was in full agreement with the ideas of that time about the work of the brain. It was already known that nervous system It is made up of nerve fibers that carry electrical signals. It was known that electrical energy can be transferred very quickly (at the speed of light), and

Page 13 of 23

therefore, our perception of the world around us with the help of nerve fibers coming from our eyes could well be almost instantaneous. The professor under whom Hermann Helmholtz studied told him that it was impossible to measure the speed of signal propagation along the nerves. It was believed that this speed is too high. But Helmholtz, as befits a good student, ignored this advice. In 1852, he was able to measure the speed of propagation of nerve signals and show that this speed is relatively low. Through the processes of sensory neurons, a nerve impulse propagates 1 meter in about 20 milliseconds. Helmholtz also measured "time of perception": he asked subjects to press a button as soon as they felt a touch on a particular part of the body. It turned out that it takes even more time, more than 100 milliseconds. These observations showed that we do not perceive the objects of the surrounding world instantly. Helmholtz realized that before any object of the surrounding world is displayed in the mind, a number of processes must go through in the brain. He put forward the idea that our perception of the world around us is not directly, but depends on "unconscious inferences." In other words, before we perceive any object, the brain must conclude what it might be for the object, based on the information coming from the senses.

Not only does it seem to us that we perceive the world instantly and effortlessly, it also seems to us that we see the entire field of vision clearly and in detail. This is also an illusion. We see in detail and in color only the central part of the visual field, the light from which enters the center of the retina. This is due to the fact that only in the center of the retina (in the fovea region) are densely packed light-sensitive neurons (cones). At an angle of about 10° from the center, the light-sensitive neurons (rods) are no longer so closely spaced and only distinguish color and shadow. At the edges of the field of view, we see the world blurry and colorless.

Normally, we are not aware of this blurring of our visual field. Our eyes are in constant motion, so that any part of the field of view can be in the center, where it will be visible in detail. But even when we think we have examined everything in sight, we are still in the grip of an illusion. In 1997, Ron Rensink and his colleagues described "change blindness" (change blindness), and since then this phenomenon has become a favorite subject for demonstrations for everyone involved in cognitive psychology these days open doors.

Rice. 2.1. In our field of view, everything except the central area is blurry.

Above is the apparent visible image.

Below is the actual visible image.

The problem with psychologists is that every person knows something about the subject of our science from personal experience. It would never occur to me to explain to someone who is into molecular genetics or nuclear physics how to interpret their data, but they are quite happy to explain to me how to interpret mine. Change-blindness is so appealing to us psychologists because it helps us show people that they personal experience deceptive. We know something about their consciousness that they themselves do not know.

The professor of English has come to our department's open day and is heroically trying not to show that she is bored. I demonstrate to her the phenomenon of blindness to change.

The demonstration includes two versions of a complex picture, between which there is one difference. In this case, it is a photograph of a military transport aircraft standing on the runway at the airport. In one version, the aircraft is missing one engine. It is located in the very center of the picture and takes up a lot of space. I show these pictures one after another on a computer screen (and, and this is important, I show a uniform gray screen in between). The English professor sees no difference. After a minute, I show the difference on the screen, and it becomes painfully obvious.

“Quite funny. But where is the science in this?

This demonstration shows that we are quickly grasping the essence of the observed picture: a military transport aircraft on a runway. But in fact, we do not keep in mind all its details. In order for the subject to notice a change in one of these details, I must draw his attention to it (“Look at the engine!”). Otherwise, he will not be able to find the changing detail until he accidentally looks at it at the moment when the picture changes. This is how change blindness arises in this psychological focus. You don't know exactly where the change is happening, and so you don't notice it.

AT real life our peripheral vision, although it gives us a blurry picture of the world, is very sensitive to changes. If the brain detects movement at the edge of the visual field, the eyes immediately turn to that side, allowing the area to be viewed. But in an experiment demonstrating change blindness, the subject sees a blank gray screen in between the pictures. In this case, the entire visible picture changes greatly, since the surface of the screen was multi-colored, and becomes completely gray.

Rice. 2.2. Blind to change

How quickly can you spot the difference between these two pictures?

So, we must come to the conclusion that our sense of instantaneous and complete perception of everything that we have in our field of vision is false. Perception occurs with a slight delay, during which the brain produces “unconscious inferences” that give us an idea of ​​the essence of the observed picture. In addition, many parts of this picture remain blurred and not visible in all details. But our brain knows that what we are seeing is not blurry, and it also knows that eye movements can show any part of the visual field sharply and distinctly at any time. Thus, the detailed visible picture of the world that seems to us reflects only what we can potentially consider in detail, and not what is already displayed in detail in our brain. immediacy

Page 14 of 23

our contact with the material world is sufficient for practical purposes. But this contact depends on our brain, and our brain, even quite healthy, does not always tell us everything it knows.

Our hidden brain

Could it be that in an experience that demonstrates blindness to change, our brain still sees the changes that occur in the picture, despite the fact that they are not visible to consciousness? Until recently, this question was very difficult to answer. Let's step away from the brain for a moment and ask ourselves if we can be affected by something we've seen but aren't aware of. In the sixties, this phenomenon was called subliminal perception, and psychologists strongly doubted its existence. On the one hand, many people believed that advertisers could introduce a hidden message into the film that would make us, for example, buy this or that drink more often, without realizing that we were being manipulated. On the other hand, many psychologists believed that there was no subliminal perception. They argued that in a properly designed experiment, the effect would be observed only if the subjects were aware of what they saw. Since then, many experiments have been carried out and no evidence has been obtained that unconsciously perceived advertising hidden in films can make us buy any drink more often. However, it has been shown that some unconsciously perceived objects can have a small effect on our behavior. But it is difficult to demonstrate this effect. To make sure that the subject is not aware that he saw some object, it is shown very quickly and "masked" it, immediately after that another object is shown in the same place.

The displayed objects are usually words or pictures on a computer screen. If the duration of the demonstration of the first object is short enough, the subject sees only the second object, but if it is too short, then there will be no effect. The first object must be shown for a strictly defined time. How to measure the impact of objects that the subject sees, but does not realize it? If you ask the subject to guess some properties of an object that he has not seen, such a request will seem strange to him. He will try his best to see the flashing image for a moment. After a number of attempts, this may work.

The whole point is that the result of the impact is preserved after the demonstration of the object. Whether this result can be tracked depends on the questions asked. Robert Zajonc showed subjects a series of unfamiliar faces, each masked by a tangle of lines so that the subjects were unaware they were seeing faces. Then he showed each of these faces again, next to another, new face. When he asked, “Guess which of these faces I just showed you?” - the subjects guessed no more often than they were wrong. But when he asked, “Which of these faces do you like best?” - they more often chose exactly the face that they had just seen unconsciously.

Rice. 2.3. Image masking

Two faces are shown on the screen, one after the other. If the interval between the first face and the second is less than approximately 40 milliseconds, the subject is unaware that he has seen the first face.

When brain-scanning CT scanners became available, researchers were able to ask a slightly different question about subthreshold perception: “Does an object cause changes in our brain activity, even if we are not aware that we are seeing it?” This question is much easier to answer because it does not require the subject to give any answers about objects he has not seen. It's enough just to watch his brain. Paul Whalen and his colleagues used a frightened face as such an object.

John Morris and his colleagues had previously established that showing a person images of faces with a frightened expression (as opposed to a happy or calm one) increased activity in the amygdala, a small area of ​​the brain that seems to be associated with monitoring dangerous situations. Whalen and his colleagues conducted similar experiments, but this time images of frightened faces were perceived only at a subthreshold level. In some cases, the subjects immediately after the frightened face were shown a calm one. In other cases, a calm face was preceded by a joyful one. In both cases, people said they saw only a calm face. But when a calm face was preceded by a frightened one, there was an increase in activity in the amygdala, despite the fact that the subject was not aware that he was seeing a frightened face.

Rice. 2.4. Our brain reacts to scary things we've seen without realizing it.

Diana Beck and her colleagues also used faces as subjects, but they based their experiments on demonstrating change blindness. In some cases, the face of one person was replaced by the face of another. In other cases, the face remained the same. The experiment was set up in such a way that the subjects noticed changes in only about half of the cases when these changes occurred. The subjects did not feel any difference between the cases when there were no changes and when there were changes that they did not notice. But their brains felt the difference. In cases where the image of the face changed to another, there was an increase in activity in the area of ​​the brain associated with the perception of faces.

So, our brain does not tell us everything it knows. But he is not capable of such a thing: sometimes he actively misleads us ...

Rice. 2.5. Our brain reacts to changes we see but are not aware of.

Sources: Redrawn from: Beck, D.M., Rees, G., Frith, C.D., & Lavie, N. (2001). Neural correlates of change detection and change blindness. Nature Neuroscience, 4(6), 645–656.

Our inadequate brain

Before the discovery of change blindness, the favorite focus of psychologists was visual illusions (deceptions of the eye). They also make it easy to demonstrate that we do not always see what is actually there. Most of these illusions are known to psychologists for more than

Page 15 of 23

hundred years, and for artists and architects much longer.

Here is one simple example: Hering's illusion.

Rice. 2.6. Goering's illusion

Even if we know that the two horizontal lines are actually straight, they appear to us to be arcuately curved. Ewald Göring, 1861

Horizontal lines appear distinctly curved. But if you put a ruler on them, you will see that they are absolutely straight. There are many other similar illusions in which straight lines appear to be curved or objects of the same size appear to be different sizes. In Hering's illusion, the background that the lines run through somehow prevents us from seeing them for what they really are. Examples of such a distorted perception can be found not only in the pages of psychology textbooks. They are also found in the objects of the material world. The most famous example is the Parthenon in Athens. The beauty of this building lies in the ideal proportions and symmetry of the straight and parallel lines of its outlines. But in reality, these lines are neither straight nor parallel. The architects introduced curves and distortions into the proportions of the Parthenon, calculated so that the building looked straight and strictly symmetrical.

To me, the most striking thing about these illusions is that my brain continues to give me false information even when I know that this information is false, and even when I know what these objects really look like. I can't bring myself to see the lines in Hering's illusion as straight. “Amendments” to the proportions of the Parthenon still work, after more than two thousand years.

The Ames Room is an even more striking example of how little our knowledge can influence our vision of the world around us.

I know that all these people are actually the same height. The one on the left seems small because it is further away from us. The room is not really rectangular. The left edge of the back wall is much further away from us than the right edge. The proportions of the windows in the back wall are distorted so that they appear rectangular (like the Parthenon). And yet my brain prefers to think of it as a rectangular room containing three people of impossibly different heights, rather than as an unusually shaped room built by someone, in which there are three people of normal height.

Rice. 2.7. The perfection of the appearance of the Parthenon is the result of an optical illusion

Schemes based on the findings of John Pennethorne (Pennethorne, 1844); deviations are greatly exaggerated.

There is at least one thing to be said to justify my brain. The appearance of the Ames room is indeed ambiguous. What we see is either three unusual people in an ordinary rectangular room, or three normal people in a strangely shaped room. The interpretation of this picture that my brain chooses may not be plausible, but it is at least a possible interpretation.

“But there is no single correct interpretation and cannot be!” says the professor of English.

I object that although our information is ambiguous, this does not mean that there can be no correct interpretation at all. And one more thing: our brain hides this possibility of a double interpretation from us and gives us only one of the possible interpretations.

Moreover, sometimes our brain does not take into account the available information about the world around us at all.

Rice. 2.8. Ames room

A 1946 invention by Adelbert Ames, Jr. based on an idea by Helmholtz.

All three people are actually the same height, but the proportions of the room are distorted.

Sources: Wittreich, W.J. (1959). Visual perception and personality, Scientific American, 200(4), 56–60(58). Photo courtesy of William Vandivert.

Our creative brain

Confusion of feelings

I know a few people who look completely normal. But they see a world different from the one I see.

As a synesthete, I live in a different world than those around me, in a world where there are more colors, shapes and sensations. In my universe, the ones are black and the environments are green, the numbers go up into the sky, and every year is like a roller coaster.

Most of us have different feelings completely separate from each other. Light waves enter our eyes and we see colors and shapes. Sound waves enter our ears and we hear words or music. But some people, called synesthetes, not only hear sounds when sound waves hit their ears, but they also experience colors. D.S., when she hears music, sees various objects in front of her: falling golden balls, flickering lines, silvery waves, like on an oscilloscope screen, which float in front of her six inches from her nose. The most common form of synesthesia is color hearing.

Every word you hear evokes a sensation of color. In most cases, this color is determined by the first letter of the word. For each synesthete, any letter and any number has its own color, and these colors remain unchanged throughout life (see Fig. 1 in the color insert). Synesthetes do not like it if the depicted letter or number is painted in the “wrong” color. For the synesthete, known by the initials G.S., the three is red and the four is cornflower blue. Carol Mills showed G.S. a series of multi-colored numbers and asked her to name their colors as quickly as possible. When the subject was shown a number of the “wrong” color (for example, a blue three), she needed more time to answer. The synesthetic color that this figure had for her interfered with the perception of her real color. This experiment gives us objective evidence that the sensations described by synesthetes are no less real than the sensations of other people. He also shows that these sensations come whether the person wants it or not. extreme forms

Page 16 of 23

synesthesia can interfere with a person's life, making it difficult to perceive words.

The late S.M. had such a voice. Eisenstein, as if some kind of flame with veins was approaching me.

Or, on the contrary, they can help.

From time to time, when I was not sure how to spell a particular word, I thought about what color it should be, and this helped me figure it out. In my opinion, this technique has helped me more than once to write correctly, both in English and in foreign languages.

Synesthetes know that the colors they see are not really there, but despite this, their brain creates a vivid and distinct sensation that they are. “And why do you say that these flowers do not really exist? asks the professor of English. - Are colors phenomena of the material world or our consciousness? If consciousness, then how is your world better than the world of your acquaintance with synesthesia?

When my friend says that these colors do not really exist, she must mean that most other people, including myself, do not feel them.

Sleeper hallucinations

Synesthesia is quite rare. But each of us has had dreams. Every night while we sleep, we experience distinct sensations and strong emotions.

I dreamed that I needed to enter the room, but I did not have the key. I went to the house, and Charles R. was standing there. The thing is, I was trying to climb in the window. Anyway, Charles was standing there at the door, and he gave me sandwiches, two sandwiches. They were red - I think with raw smoked ham, and he had boiled pork. I didn't understand why he gave me the worse ones. Anyway, after that he entered the room, and something was not right there. Looks like there was some sort of party going on. I guess that's when I began to think about how quickly I could get out of there, if necessary. And there was something to do with nitroglycerin, I don't really remember. The last thing I remember is someone throwing a baseball.

Despite the fact that the sensations experienced in a dream are so distinct, we remember only a small part of them (about 5%).

“But how do you know that I have so many dreams, even if I myself cannot remember them?” asks the professor of English.

In the 1950s, Eugene Aserinsky and Nathaniel Kleitman discovered special phase sleep during which rapid eye movement occurs. Different phases of sleep are associated with different forms of brain activity, which can be measured using the EEG. During one of these phases, our brain activity on the EEG looks exactly the same as during wakefulness. But at the same time, all our muscles are, in fact, paralyzed, and we cannot move. The only exception is the muscles of the eyes. During this phase of sleep, the eyes move rapidly from side to side, despite the fact that the eyelids remain closed. This is the so-called phase of REM sleep, or REM phase (rapid eye movement phase). If I wake you up during REM sleep, you will most likely (with a 90% probability) say that you were watching a dream when you were awakened, and you will be able to remember many details of this dream. However, if I wake you up five minutes after the end of REM sleep, you will not remember any dreams. These experiments show how quickly dreams are erased from our memory. We remember them only when we wake up during or immediately after REM sleep. But I can tell you're dreaming by monitoring your eye movements and your brain activity while you sleep.

Wakefulness: fast, asynchronous nerve activity, muscle activity, eye movement

Non-REM sleep: slow, synchronous nerve activity, some muscle activity, no eye movement, few dreams

REM sleep: REM, non-synchronous neural activity, paralysis, no muscle activity, rapid eye movement, many dreams

The pictures that the brain shows us during dreams do not reflect the objects of the material world. But we perceive them so clearly that some people have wondered if they are accessing some other reality in their dreams. Twenty-four centuries ago Chuang Tzu had a dream in which he was a butterfly. “I dreamed that I was a butterfly fluttering from flower to flower and knowing nothing about Chuang Tzu.” Waking up, he, according to him, did not know who he was - a man who dreamed that he was a butterfly, or a butterfly who dreamed that she was a man.

Robert Frost's dream about the apples he just picked

... And I comprehended

What a vision the soul languished.

All apples are huge and round,

flickered around me

A pink blush from the mist,

And the shin and foot ached

From stairs, rungs.

Suddenly I shook the stairs sharply ...

(Excerpt from the poem “After picking apples”, 1914)

Usually the content of our dreams is implausible enough for us to confuse the dream with reality (see figure 4 in color inset). For example, there are often inconsistencies between the appearance of people we see in a dream and their real prototypes. “I was talking to my colleague (in my dream), but she looked different, much younger, like one of the girls I went to school with, about thirteen years old.” However, during sleep, we are convinced that everything that happens to us is actually happening. And only at the moment of awakening do we realize, usually with relief, that “it was only a dream. I don't have to run away from anyone."

Hallucinations in healthy people

Synesthetes are unusual people. When we dream, our brain is also in an unusual state. To what extent the brain of an ordinary, physically healthy person in the waking state is able to create something

Page 17 of 23

similar? This was the subject of a large-scale study involving 17,000 people conducted in late XIX century by the Society for Psychical Research. The main goal of this society was to find evidence for the existence of telepathy, that is, the transmission of thoughts directly from one person to another without any obvious material intermediaries. It was believed that such a transmission of thoughts at a distance is especially likely in a state of strong emotional stress.

On October 5, 1863, I woke up at five o'clock in the morning. It was at Minto House Normal School in Edinburgh. I distinctly heard the characteristic and well-known voice of one of my close friends, repeating the words of a famous church hymn. Nothing was visible. I lay in bed fully conscious, in good health, and not disturbed by anything in particular. At the same time, almost at the same moment, my friend was suddenly stricken with a fatal illness. He died on the same day, and on the same evening I received a telegram announcing this.

Today, psychologists treat such claims with extreme distrust. But at that time, the Society for Psychical Research included several eminent scientists in its ranks. The chairman of the commission overseeing this "census of hallucinations" was Professor Henry Sidgwick, the Cambridge philosopher and founder of Newham College. The collection of materials was carried out with great care, and a report published in 1894 included the results of a detailed statistical analysis. The compilers of the report tried to exclude from it data on sensations that could be the fruits of dreams or delusions associated with bodily diseases, or hallucinations associated with mental illnesses. They also went to great lengths to draw the line between hallucinations and illusions.

Here is the exact question they asked the respondents:

Have you ever experienced, while fully conscious, the distinct sensation that you are seeing or touching a living being or an inanimate object, or hearing a voice, although this sensation, as far as you could determine, was not due to any external physical influence?

The published report is almost 400 pages long and consists mostly of the actual words of the respondents describing their feelings. Ten percent of the respondents experienced hallucinations, and most of these hallucinations were visual (over 80%). For me, the most interesting cases are those that have no obvious relation to telepathy.

From Mrs. Girdlestone, January 1891

For several months in 1886 and 1887, as I walked down the stairs of our Clifton house in broad daylight, I felt, more than saw, a multitude of animals (mostly cats) passing me and pushing me aside.

Mrs Girdlestone writes:

The hallucinations consisted of hearing my name called so clearly that I turned around to see where the sound was coming from, whether it was a figment of the imagination or a memory of how this happened in the past, this voice, if you can call it that, had a completely inexpressible quality that invariably frightened me and separated it from ordinary sounds. This went on for several years. I have no explanation for these circumstances.

If she were to describe such experiences to her therapist today, he would most likely suggest that she undergo a neurological examination.

I also find interesting cases classified as illusions: their origin was clearly connected with the physical phenomena of the material world.

From Dr. J. J. Stoney

A few years ago, on an unusually dark summer evening, my friend and I rode bicycles—he on a two-wheeler, I on a three-wheeler—from Glendalough to Rathdrum. It was drizzling, we had no streetlights, and the road was obscured by trees standing on either side of it, between which the horizon line was barely visible. I was riding slowly and carefully, about ten or twelve yards ahead of me on the horizon, when my bike went over some tin or something like that on the road and there was a loud bang. My companion immediately drove up and called out to me in extreme anxiety. He saw through the darkness how my bike turned over and I flew out of the saddle. The ringing made him think of the most probable cause of it, and at the same time a visible picture arose in his mind, faint, but in this case sufficient to see it distinctly, when it was not overpowered by objects normally visible to the human eye.

In this example, Dr. Stoney's friend saw an event that didn't actually happen. According to Dr. Stoney, the expected picture created a visual image strong enough in the mind of his friend to see him before his eyes. In terms that I would use, his friend's brain created a plausible interpretation of what happened, and this interpretation he saw as a real event.

From Miss W.

One evening, at dusk, I went into my bedroom to get one thing from the mantelpiece. A slanting beam of light from a lantern fell through the window, which barely made it possible to see the vague outlines of the main pieces of furniture that were in the room. I cautiously felt for the thing I had come for, when, turning slightly, I saw behind me, not far from me, the figure of a little old woman, sitting very sedately, with her hands clasped in her lap, and holding a white handkerchief. I was very frightened, because before that I had not seen anyone in the room, and cried out: “Who is there?” -

Page 18 of 23

but no one answered, and when I turned face to face with my guest, she immediately disappeared from view ...

In most stories about ghosts and spirits, the story would end there, but Miss W persisted.

Since I am very nearsighted, at first I thought it was just an optical illusion, so I returned to my search for the opportunity in the same position and when I found what I was looking for, I began to turn around to leave, and suddenly - here are the miracles ! - I saw this old woman again, clearly, as never before, with her funny cap and dark dress, with meekly folded hands, clutching a white handkerchief. This time, I quickly turned around and resolutely approached the vision, which disappeared just as suddenly as the last time.

So, the effect was reproducible. What was his reason?

Now, convinced that this is not a hoax, I decided to investigate, as far as possible, the causes and nature of this riddle. Slowly returning and taking up my former position by the fireplace and seeing the same figure again, I slowly turned my head from side to side and noticed that she was doing the same. Then I slowly walked backwards, without changing the position of my head, reached the same place, slowly, turned around - and the riddle was solved.

A small lacquered mahogany bedside table standing near the window, in which I kept various trinkets, seemed to be the body of an old woman, a sheet of paper sticking out of its half-open door played the role of a handkerchief, a vase standing on the bedside table looked like a head in a cap, and an oblique beam of light falling on it , along with a white curtain on the window, completed the illusion. I dismantled and reassembled this figure several times and marveled at how clearly it was visible when all the components occupied exactly the same position in relation to each other.

Miss W.'s brain incorrectly deduced that the set of objects in the dark room was a little old woman sitting sedately by the window. Miss W. doubted this. But notice how much she had to work to figure out this illusion. At first, she doubted that what she was seeing was true. She didn't expect to meet anyone in this room. Sometimes her eyes deceive her. Then she experiments with her perception, looking at this "old woman" from different positions. How easy it is to be deceived by such an illusion! But very often we do not have the opportunity to experiment with our perception, and there is no reason to believe that our sensations are deceptive.

Edgar Allan Poe describes his fear of the "dead head"

At the end of a very hot day, I sat with a book in my hands near an open window overlooking the banks of the river and a distant hill. Looking up from the page, I saw a bare slope, and on it a hideous-looking monster, which quickly descended from the hill and disappeared into the dense forest at its foot.

The size of the monster, which I judged from the trunks of the huge trees through which it moved, was much larger than any of the ocean ships. His mouth was placed at the end of a trunk sixty or seventy feet long, and about the thickness of an elephant's body. At the base of the trunk were tufts of thick black hair, more than on the skins of a dozen buffaloes. On either side of the trunk ran a gigantic horn thirty or forty feet high, prismatic and crystalline, reflecting the rays of the setting sun dazzlingly. The body was wedge-shaped and pointed down. From it came two pairs of wings, each nearly a hundred yards long; they were located one above the other and were completely covered with metal scales. I noticed that the top pair was connected to the bottom thick chain. But the main feature of this terrible creature was the image of a skull, which occupied almost the entire of its chest and brightly whitened on its dark body, as if carefully drawn by an artist. While I was looking at the terrifying animal, the huge jaws, which were located at the end of its trunk, suddenly opened, and from them came a loud and mournful cry, which sounded in my ears with an ominous omen; As soon as the monster disappeared at the bottom of the hill, I fell senseless to the floor.

[The owner of Po's house explains:] Let me read you the description of the genus Sphinx, family Crepuscularia, order Lepidoptera, class Insecta, i.e. insects. Here is the description:

“The Death's Head Sphinx sometimes inspires considerable fear in unenlightened people because of the mournful sound it makes and the emblems of death on its shield.”

He closed the book and leaned forward to find the exact position I was in when I saw the monster.

- Well, yes, here it is! he exclaimed. “Now it is creeping up, and I must admit it looks unusual. However, it is not as large and not as far away from you as you imagined. I see that it is no more than one sixteenth of an inch long, and the same distance, one sixteenth of an inch, separates it from my pupil.

(Excerpts from the story "The Sphinx", 1850)

This chapter shows that even a normal, healthy brain does not always give us a true picture of the world. Due to the fact that we do not have a direct connection with the material world around us, our brain has to draw conclusions about the world based on raw data received from the eyes, ears and all other senses. These conclusions may be erroneous. Moreover, our brain knows a lot of all sorts of things that do not reach our consciousness at all.

But there is one piece of the material world that we always invariably carry with us. After all, at least we have direct access to information about the state of our own body? Or is this also an illusion created by our brain?

3. What our brain tells us about our body

Privileged access?

My body is an object of the material world. But I have a special relationship with my own body, not the same as with other material objects. In particular, my brain is also part of my body. The processes of sensory neurons lead directly to the brain. Outgrowths of motor neurons lead from the brain to all my muscles. These are very direct connections. I have direct control over everything my body does, and I don't need any inference to understand what state it is in. I have almost instant access to any part of my body at any given time.

So why do I still get a little shock when I see a plump old man in the mirror? Maybe I don't really know much about myself? Or is my memory forever corrupted by vanity?

Where is the border?

My first mistake is the thought that there is a clear difference between my body and the rest of the material world. Here is a little party trick invented by Matthew Botvinick and Jonathan Cohen. you put left hand on the table, and I cover it with a screen. On the same table, I place a rubber hand in front of you so that you can see it. Then I touch both your hand and the rubber hand at the same time with two brushes. You feel your hand being touched and you see a rubber hand being touched. But after a few minutes, you will no longer feel the touch of the brush where it touches your hand. You will feel it where it touches the rubber hand. The sensation will somehow go beyond your body and pass into an object of the world around you separate from you.

Such tricks performed by our brain are not only suitable for parties. In the parietal lobes of the cortex of some monkeys (presumably humans too) there are neurons that are activated when the monkey sees something near its hand. It doesn't matter where her brush is at the same time. Neurons are activated when something is in close proximity to it. Apparently, these neurons indicate the presence of objects that the monkey can reach with his hand. But if you give a monkey a paddle to use, very soon those same neurons will start responding whenever the monkey sees anything near the end of that paddle. For this part of the brain, the shoulder blade becomes like an extension of the monkey's hand. This is how we feel the tools we use. With a little practice, we get the feeling that we control the tool as directly as if it were part of our body. This applies to things as small as a fork and as big as a car.

Rice. 3.2. Monkey and shovel

If a monkey sees anything within range, the activity of certain neurons in its parietal cortex increases. Atsushi Iriki taught monkeys how to use a shovel to get food that was out of reach for their hands. When a monkey uses such a shovel, the parietal lobe neurons respond in exactly the same way to objects located within the reach of a hand armed with a shovel.

The famous British neuroscientist Chris Frith is well known for his ability to talk simply about very complex problems of psychology - such as mental activity, social behavior, autism and schizophrenia. It is in this area, along with the study of how we perceive the world around us, act, make choices, remember and feel, that today there is a scientific revolution associated with the introduction of neuroimaging methods.

Chris Frith. Brain and Soul: How Nervous Activity Shapes Our Inner World. - M.: Astrel: CORPUS, 2010. - 336 p.

Download abstract (summary) in format or

Prologue: Real Scientists Don't Study Consciousness

Whether we are awake or asleep, the 15 billion nerve cells (neurons) in our brain are constantly sending signals to each other. This consumes a lot of energy. Our brain consumes about 20% of the energy of the entire body, despite the fact that its mass is only about 2% of body weight. The entire brain is permeated with a network of blood vessels, through which energy is transferred in the form of oxygen contained in the blood. The distribution of energy in the brain is very finely tuned, so that more of it flows into those parts of the brain that are most active at the moment. Functional tomographs allow you to record the energy consumption of brain tissues.

This solves the problem of psychology as an "inexact" science. Now we have no need to worry about the inaccuracy, the subjectivity of our information about mental phenomena. Instead, we can make accurate, objective measurements of brain activity. Probably, now I will not be ashamed to admit that I am a psychologist. However, no such device will allow us to see what is happening in the inner world of another person. The objects of the inner world do not really exist.

In this book, I am going to show that there really is no difference between the inner world of man and the material world. The difference between them is an illusion created by our brain. Everything that we know, both about the material world and about the inner world of other people, we know thanks to the brain. But the connection of our brain with the material world of physical bodies is just as indirect as its connection with the non-material world of ideas. Hiding from us all the unconscious conclusions to which it comes, our brain creates in us the illusion of direct contact with the material world. At the same time, it gives us the illusion that our inner world is separate and belongs only to us. These two illusions give us the feeling that in the world we live in, we are acting as independent agents. At the same time, we can share our experience of perceiving the world around us with other people. Over the millennia, this ability to share experiences has created human culture, which in turn can influence how our brains work. By overcoming these illusions created by the brain, we can lay the foundation for a science that will explain to us how the brain shapes our consciousness.

Rice. 1. General view and section of the human brain. Human brain, side view (top). The arrow marks the place where the cut shown in the bottom photo passed. The outer layer of the brain (cortex) is composed of gray matter and forms many folds to fit large area surfaces on a small scale. The cortex contains about 10 billion nerve cells.

PART ONE. What is behind the illusions of our brain
Chapter l. What can a damaged brain tell us?

Everything that happens in the inner world (mental activity) is caused by brain activity, or at least depends on it. Brain damage makes it difficult to transmit information about the world that is collected by the senses. The nature of the impact of these damages on our ability to cognize the world around us is determined by the stage of information transfer at which the damage affects.

Observations of people with brain damage suggest that our brain may know something about the world around us that our consciousness does not. Mel Goodale and David Milner studied the woman known by the initials D.F. The experimenter held a stick in his hand and asked D.F. how the stick was positioned. She couldn't tell if the wand was horizontal or vertical or at some angle. It seemed that she did not see the wand at all and was just trying to guess its location. The experimenter then asked her to reach out and take hold of the stick with her hand. It worked out fine for her. At the same time, she turned her hand in advance so that it was more convenient to take the wand. At whatever angle the wand was placed, she could grab it with her hand without any problems. This observation shows that the brain of D.F. “knows” at what angle the wand is located, and can use this information by controlling the movements of her hand. But D.F. cannot use this information to recognize where the wand is located. Her brain knows something about the world around her that her consciousness does not know.

Chapter 2. What a healthy brain tells us about the world

It may seem to us that we directly perceive the world around us, but this is an illusion created by our brain.

Hermann Helmholtz in 1852 put forward the idea that our perception of the world around us is not directly, but depends on "unconscious inferences." In other words, before we perceive any object, the brain must conclude what it might be for the object, based on the information coming from the senses.

Psychologists' favorite tricks are visual illusions (optical illusions). They demonstrate that we do not always see what is actually there (Fig. 2).

Rice. 2. Illusion of Goering. Even if we know that the two horizontal lines are actually straight, they appear to us to be arcuately curved. Ewald Göring, 1861

Examples of such a distorted perception can be found not only in the pages of psychology textbooks. They are also found in the objects of the material world. The most famous example is the Parthenon in Athens. The beauty of this building lies in the ideal proportions and symmetry of the straight and parallel lines of its outlines. But in reality, these lines are neither straight nor parallel. The architects introduced bends and distortions into the proportions of the Parthenon, calculated so that the building looked straight and strictly symmetrical (Fig. 3).

Rice. 3. The perfection of the appearance of the Parthenon is the result of an optical illusion. Schemes based on the findings of John Pennethorne (1844); deviations are greatly exaggerated.

In the 1950s, Eugene Aserinsky and Nathaniel Kleitman discovered a special phase of sleep during which rapid eye movement occurs. During this phase, our brain activity on the EEG looks exactly the same as during wakefulness. But at the same time, all our muscles are, in fact, paralyzed, and we cannot move. The only exception is the muscles of the eyes. During this phase of sleep, the eyes move rapidly from side to side, despite the fact that the eyelids remain closed (Fig. 4).

Rice. 4. Phases of sleep. (i) wakefulness: fast, asynchronous neural activity; muscle activity; eye movement; (ii) non-REM sleep: slow, synchronous neural activity; some muscle activity; no eye movement; few dreams; (iii) REM sleep: fast, non-synchronous neural activity; paralysis, no muscle activity; rapid eye movement many dreams

  1. What our brain tells us about our body

In 1983, Benjamin Libet conducted an experiment. All that was required of the subjects was to raise one finger whenever they "would like to do it." In the meantime, the electrical activity of the brain was measured using an EEG machine. The main discovery was that the change in brain activity occurred about 500 milliseconds before a person lifted a finger, and the desire to lift a finger occurs about 200 milliseconds before a person lifts a finger. Thus, brain activity indicated that the subject was about to raise his finger 300 milliseconds before the subject reported that he was going to raise his finger.

This result generated such interest outside the psychological community because it seemed to show that even our simplest conscious actions are actually predetermined. We think we are making a choice, when in fact our brain has already made that choice. But this does not mean that this choice was not made freely. It simply means that we are not aware that we are making a choice at this earlier point in time (Sam Harris in his book concluded differently, believing that the experiment showed the absence of free will).

Rice. 5. Mental events that determine our movements do not occur simultaneously with physical events. The brain activity associated with a particular movement begins before we are aware of our intention to make this movement, but the movement "starts" after we realize that we are starting it.

As we will see after reading the sixth chapter, our perception of the time of performing certain actions is not strictly tied to what is happening in the material world.

Imagine that you are sitting in the dark. I'm showing you a glimpse of a black spot within the frame. Immediately after that, I again briefly show you a black spot within the frame. The spot does not change its position, but the frame is shifted to the right (Fig. 6). If I ask you to describe what you see, you will say: "The spot has moved to the left." This is a typical visual illusion associated with the fact that the visual areas of the brain mistakenly decided that the frame remained in place, which means that the spot should have moved. But if I ask you to touch the spot where the spot originally was, then you will touch the correct spot on the screen - no amount of frame movement will prevent you from pointing to that spot correctly. Your hand "knows" that the stain hasn't moved, even though you think it has.

Rice. 6. Illusion Roelofs. If the frame is shifted to the right, the observer appears to have moved the black spot to the left, even though it has remained in place. But if the observer stretches out his hand to touch the position of the spot imprinted in memory, he does not make such a mistake.

These observations demonstrate that our body can perfectly interact with the outside world even when we ourselves do not know what it is doing, and even when our ideas about the world around us are not true. It may be that our brain is directly connected to our body, but the information supplied by the brain about the state of our body seems to be of the same indirect nature as the information supplied to us about the world around us.

Until the 1980s, neurophysiologists were taught that after we reach the age of about sixteen, the brain matures and growth stops completely. If the fibers connecting some neurons are destroyed, these neurons will forever remain disconnected. If you lose a neuron, it will never recover. Now we know that this is not the case. Our brains are very plastic, especially when we are young, and remain so throughout our lives. Connections between neurons are constantly being made and broken in response to changes in the environment.

PART TWO. How does our brain do it?
Chapter 4

This is how Bayes' theorem is stated:

Take some phenomenon (A) that we want to know about, and an observation (X) that gives us some information about A. Bayes' theorem tells us how much our knowledge of A will increase in light of new information X. This equation gives us exactly that mathematical formula the belief we were looking for. Belief in this case corresponds to the mathematical concept of probability. Probability measures how much I believe in something.

Bayes' theorem shows exactly how much my belief about A will change in the light of new information X. In the equation above, p(A) is my initial or a priori belief about A before new information X, p(X|A) is the probability of obtaining information X in case A actually takes place, and p(A|X) is my subsequent, or a posteriori, belief about A given the new information X.

The ideal Bayesian observer. The importance of Bayes' theorem is that it enables us to measure very precisely the extent to which new information should change our understanding of the world. Bayes' theorem gives us a criterion for judging whether we are adequately using new knowledge. This is the basis of the concept of the ideal Bayesian observer - an imaginary being who always uses the information received in the best possible way.

But there is another aspect of Bayes' theorem that is even more important for understanding how our brains work. There are two key elements in Bayes' formula: p(A|X) and p(X|A). The p(A|X) value tells us how much we should change our understanding of the world around us (A) after receiving new information (X). p(X|A) tells us what information (X) we should expect based on our belief (A). We can look at these elements as tools that allow our brains to make predictions and track errors in them. Guided by our ideas about the world around us, our brain can predict the nature of events that our eyes, ears and other senses will follow: p(X|A). What happens when such a prediction turns out to be wrong? Tracking errors in such predictions is especially important because our brains can use them to refine and improve our understanding of the world around us: p(A|X). After making such a refinement, the brain gets a new idea of ​​the world and can repeat the same procedure again, making a new prediction about the nature of the events tracked by the senses. With each repetition of this cycle, the error in the predictions decreases. When the error is small enough, our brain “knows” what is going on around us. And all this happens so fast that we are not even aware of the entire complex procedure. It may seem to us that ideas about what is happening around us come easily, but they require the brain to relentlessly repeat these cycles of predictions and clarifications.

Our perceptions depend on a priori beliefs. It is not a linear process, like the ones that produce images in a photograph or on a TV screen. For our brain, perception is a cycle. If our perception were linear, energy in the form of light or sound waves would reach the senses, these messages from the outside world would be translated into the language of nerve signals, and the brain would interpret them as objects occupying a certain position in space. It was this approach that made perceptual modeling on first-generation computers such a challenge.

A predictive brain does almost the exact opposite. Our perception actually starts from within - with an a priori belief, which is a model of the world where objects occupy a certain position in space. Using this model, our brain can predict what signals should go to our eyes and ears. These predictions are compared with real signals, and in doing so, of course, errors are found. But our brain only welcomes them. These mistakes teach him perception. The presence of such errors tells him that his model of the world around him is not good enough. The nature of the errors tells him how to make a model that will be better than the previous one. As a result, the cycle repeats again and again, until the errors become negligible. This usually takes only a few such cycles, for which the brain may need only 100 milliseconds.

Where does our brain get the a priori knowledge necessary for perception? Some of this is innate knowledge, stored in our brains over millions of years of evolution. For example, for many millions of years there was only one main source of light on our planet - the Sun. And sunlight always falls from above. This means that concave objects will be darker at the top and lighter at the bottom, while convex objects will be lighter at the top and darker at the bottom. This simple rule is hard-coded into our brains. With its help, the brain decides whether an object is convex or concave (Fig. 8).

Rice. 8. Illusion with dominoes. Above - a half of a domino with five concave spots and one convex one. Below - a half with two concave and four convex spots. You are actually looking at a flat sheet of paper. The spots look concave or convex due to the nature of their shading. We expect the light to come from above, so a convex spot should have its bottom edge shaded, while a concave spot should have its top edge shaded. If you flip the pattern upside down, the concave spots become convex and the convex ones become concave:

Modern technologies allow us to create many new images, which our brain is not able to correctly interpret. We inevitably perceive such images incorrectly.

What we perceive is not those raw and ambiguous signals coming from the outside world to our eyes, ears and fingers. Our perception is much richer - it combines all these raw signals with the treasures of our experience. Our perception is a prediction of what should be in the world around us. And this prediction is constantly tested by actions.

But any system, when it fails, makes certain characteristic mistakes. What mistakes will a system that works by predictions make? She will have problems in any situation that allows for an ambiguous interpretation. Such problems are usually solved by making one of the possible interpretations much more likely than the other. Many of the visual illusions that psychologists love so much work precisely because they trick our brains in this way (see for an excellent illustration).

The very odd shape of the Ames room is designed to evoke the same visual sensations, as an ordinary rectangular room (Fig. 9). Both models, the oddly shaped room and the regular rectangular room, are equally good at predicting what our eyes see. But in experience we have dealt with rectangular rooms so much more often that we inevitably see the Ames room as rectangular, and it seems to us that people who move from corner to corner in it increase and decrease in an unthinkable way. The a priori probability (expectation) that we are looking at a room of such a strange shape is so small that our Bayesian brain does not take into account unusual information about the possibility of such a room.

Our brain builds models of the world around us and constantly changes these models based on the signals that reach our senses. Therefore, in fact, we do not perceive the world itself, but its models created by our brain. We can say that our sensations are fantasies that coincide with reality. Moreover, in the absence of signals from the senses, our brain finds how to fill in the gaps that arise in the incoming information. There is a blind spot in the retina of our eyes where there are no photoreceptors. It is located where all the nerve fibers that carry signals from the retina to the brain come together to form the optic nerve. There is no place for photoreceptors there. We don't realize that we have this blind spot because our brain always finds something to fill this part of the visual field with. Our brain uses signals from the area of ​​the retina immediately surrounding the blind spot to make up for this lack of information.

Chapter 6

The ability to see the movement of living objects is deeply rooted in our brain. As early as six months of age, infants prefer to look at moving luminous dots that form a human figure, rather than dots that move similarly but are randomly placed (Fig. 10).

We pay special attention to the eyes of other people. When we follow someone's eyes, we catch their slightest movements. This sensitivity to eye movements allows us to take the first step into the inner world of another person. From the position of his eyes, we can tell quite accurately where he is looking. And if we know where a person is looking, we can find out what he is interested in.

We not only unwittingly look at what others look at. Our brain has a tendency to automatically repeat any movement that we see. Giacomo Rizzolatti and his colleagues conducted experiments in Parma on the neurons involved in the grasping movements of monkeys. To the researchers' surprise, some of these neurons didn't just fire when the monkey touched something. They were also activated when the monkey saw one of the experimenters take something with his hand. Such neurons are now called mirror neurons. The same is true for the human brain.

Imitation is like prediction. We have a tendency to imitate others automatically without thinking about it. But imitation also gives us access to the personal inner world of others. We imitate not only the rough movements of the arms and legs. We also automatically imitate the subtle movements of faces. And this imitation of other people's faces affects our feelings. Due to the fact that we can build models of the material world, we are able to share the sensations of the inner world of other people.

Our ability to create models of the inner world entails some problems. Our picture of the material world is a fantasy, limited by the signals coming from the senses. In the same way, our picture of the inner world (our own or other people) is a fantasy, limited by the signals we receive about what we ourselves say and do (or about what others say and do). When these restrictions fail, we have illusions about what we do and see.

PART THREE. Culture and brain
Chapter 7

The most remarkable achievement of our brain is undoubtedly its ability to provide communication between consciousnesses. different people. I have an idea in my head that I would like to share with you. I do this by translating the meaning of this idea into spoken language. You hear my speech and again transform it into an idea in your head. But how do you know that the idea in your head is the same as the one in my head?

The problem of words and meanings is a more complicated version of the problem of movements and intentions. When I see movement, I capture the intention behind it. But the meaning of the movements is ambiguous. Many different goals require the same movements. Engineers would call this search for meaning an inverse problem. Our hand is a simple mechanical device that engineers can understand. It is based on solid rods (bones) connected by joints. We move the arm by applying muscle power to these rods. What happens when we apply a force to this system in a certain way? The search for an answer to this question is called the direct problem. This problem has a unique solution.

But there is also an inverse problem. What forces do we need to apply if we want our hand to take a certain position? This problem does not have a single solution. We solve exactly the same inverse problem when we listen to human speech. To express many different meanings you can use the same words. How do we choose the best of these meanings? We (more precisely, our brain) make assumptions about what goals this or that person can pursue, and then predict what he will do next. We assume that a person is trying to tell us something, and then we predict what he will say next.

Where do our assumptions begin? Assumptions about people about whom we do not yet know anything can only be based on prejudice. This is nothing but prejudice. Prejudices give us the opportunity to start making assumptions - no matter how accurate our guess turns out to be, as long as we always adjust our next guess according to the error we discover. Prejudice is built into our brains by evolution. We have an innate tendency to prejudice. All our social interactions begin with prejudice. The content of these prejudices is obtained from interactions with friends and acquaintances, as well as from rumors.

Our prejudices start with stereotypes. Our first a priori beliefs about the likely knowledge and behavior of strangers are related to their gender. Even three-year-old children have already developed this prejudice.

Social stereotypes give us a starting point for interactions with strangers. They allow us to make first guesses about the intentions of these people. But we know that these stereotypes are very primitive. The assumptions and predictions we make based on such limited knowledge will not be very good.

Communication in the form of a dialogue, face to face, is not a one-way process, unlike reading a book. When I have a dialogue with you, depending on your reaction to me, my reaction to you changes. This is the cycle of communication.

We understand that people's behavior is driven by beliefs, even if those beliefs are false. And we quickly learn that we can control people's behavior by giving them false information. This is dark side our communication. Without the realization that behavior can be controlled by beliefs, even if those beliefs are false, deliberate deceit and lying would be impossible. At first glance, a person's inability to lie may seem like a nice, pleasant quality. However, often such people are lonely and have no friends. Friendships are actually maintained through many little lies and evasive answers that allow us to sometimes hide our true feelings. At the other extreme, people suffering from paranoia are represented, any message can be a deception or a hidden message that requires interpretation.

True. Our knowledge of the world is no longer limited to the experience of one lifetime - it is passed down from generation to generation. I believe that truth exists. As long as we can be convinced that one model of the material world works better than another, we can strive to create a series of more and more successful models. At the end of this series, although it is infinite in the mathematical sense, is the truth - the truth of how the world really works. The achievement of this truth is the task of science.

That is why the belief of some philosophers in the purity of sensory perception is devoid of practical meaning. There is simply no such thing as "sense perception". Perception is always preceded by theory.

What a pity that we prefer email to dialogue.

Brain and soul. How neural activity shapes our inner world Chris Frith

(No ratings yet)

Title: Brain and Soul. How neural activity shapes our inner world

About the book “Brain and Soul. How neural activity shapes our inner world." Chris Frith

The famous British neuroscientist Chris Frith is well known for his ability to talk simply about very complex problems of psychology - such as mental activity, social behavior, autism and schizophrenia. It is in this area, along with the study of how we perceive the world around us, act, make choices, remember and feel, that today there is a scientific revolution associated with the introduction of neuroimaging methods. In Brain and Soul, Chris Frith talks about all this in the most accessible and entertaining way.

On our site about books, you can download the site for free without registration or read online book“Brain and soul. How neural activity shapes our inner world" by Chris Frith in epub, fb2, txt, rtf, pdf formats for iPad, iPhone, Android and Kindle. The book will give you a lot of pleasant moments and a real pleasure to read. Buy full version you can have our partner. Also, here you will find the latest news from the literary world, learn the biography of your favorite authors. For novice writers, there is a separate section with useful tips and tricks, interesting articles, thanks to which you can try your hand at writing.

Quotes from the book “Brain and Soul. How neural activity shapes our inner world." Chris Frith

And yet, in everyday life, we are as interested in the thoughts of other people as in the objects of the material world. We interact with other people by exchanging thoughts with them, much more than we physically interact with their bodies. By reading this book, you will know my thoughts. And I, in turn, write it in the hope that it will allow me to change the way you think.

The consequences of damage to the primary visual cortex depend on where exactly the injury occurred. If the upper left part of the visual cortex is damaged, then the patient is unable to see objects located in the lower right part of the visual field. In this part of the visual field, such patients are blind.

There is a deep connection between our perception of ourselves as free agents and our willingness to act altruistically, rejoicing when we ourselves act honestly and upset when others act dishonestly. For these feelings to arise, it is essential that we perceive ourselves and others as free agents. We believe that we are all capable of making informed choices. This is the basis of our willingness to cooperate with others. This final illusion created by our brains is that we exist separately from social environment and being free agents, allows us together to create a society and culture that is so much greater than each of us individually.

They are able to see and describe the various characteristics of an object, but do not understand what it is. This impairment of recognition is called agnosia.

But whatever it is, we can conclude that in our minds there can be no knowledge about the world around us that is not represented in the brain in any way.

This disease is associated with a disorder of the brain, as a result of which the electrical activity of a large number of neurons gets out of control from time to time, causing a seizure (seizure).

Do not believe what others tell you, no matter how high their authority may be.

Whether we are awake or asleep, the 15 billion nerve cells (neurons) in our brain are constantly sending signals to each other.

But with the CT scanner, I can get into his brain. And I can see that when he imagines walking down the street and turning left, there is activity in his brain of a certain kind.

Our brain consumes about 20% of the energy of the entire body, despite the fact that its mass is only about 2% of body weight.

Free download of the book “Brain and Soul. How neural activity shapes our inner world." Chris Frith

(Fragment)


In the format fb2: Download
In the format rtf: Download
In the format epub: Download
In the format txt: